Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  •  36
    Rationality: A comment on Raymond Boudon's paper
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (1). 1993.
  •  60
    Rationality and the tu quoque argument
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-4). 1973.
    The tu quoque argument is the argument that since in the end rationalism rests on an irrational choice of and commitment to rationality, rationalism is as irrational as any other commitment. Popper's and Polanyi's philosophies of science both accept the argument, and have on that account many similarities; yet Popper manages to remain a rationalist whereas Polanyi decided for an irrationalist version of rationalism. This is more marked in works of their respective followers, W. W. Bartley III an…Read more
  •  9
    Review (review)
    Erkenntnis 13 (1). 1978.
  •  27
    Review: Duhem versus Galileo (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 8 (31). 1957.
  •  57
    Replies
    Synthese 30 (1-2). 1975.
  •  27
    Rationality: Philosophical and social aspects (review)
    Minerva 30 (3): 366-390. 1992.
  •  27
    is an unusual phenomenon. The concern with rights different citizens have in different societies is legal rather than philosophical. It is frequently somewhat a technical matter for jurisprudence to decide exactly what rights a citizen has in a given situation and how he might best exercise his rights. Often, to be sure, the legal technicalities involve matters of principle, and if so these should be made explicit. For this, too, there is a need less for philosophy and more for jurisprudence, fo…Read more
  • Russell Kahl , "Studies in Explanation" (review)
    Philosophical Forum 23 (n/a): 49. 1965.
  •  9
    Review: A Hegelian View of Complementarity (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 9 (33). 1958.
  •  21
    The context of a scientific theory can be epistemological and methodological. Or it car be metaphysical, relating to the intellectual framework within which we cast it. Or it can be intertheoretical, both synchronically and diachronically. My concern here will be mainly diachronical -- the historical context of quantum theory, what is required of it vis -a-vis that context and how well it fulfills this requirement. But I shall come to this only at the later part of this essay. I shall have to cl…Read more
  • Philosophie als Lebenshilfe?
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 28 (72): 83-92. 1995.
  •  76
    Presuppositions for Logic
    The Monist 65 (4): 465-480. 1982.
    Positivists identify science and certainty and in the name of the utter rationality of science deny that it rests on speculative presuppositions. The Logical Positivists took a step further and tried to show such presuppositions really no presuppositions at all but rather poorly worded sentences. Rules of sentence formation, however, rest on the presuppositions about the nature of language. This makes us unable to determine the status of mathematics, which is these days particularly irksome sinc…Read more
  •  3
    Reviews (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38 (3): 414-418. 1987.
  •  41
    Precision in theory and in measurement
    Philosophy of Science 35 (3): 287-290. 1968.
    An intuitive idea concerning degrees of precision is widely accepted, and it is that we increase precision of theories by paying attention to ever decreasing orders of magnitude of measurements which we incorporate in these theories. We increase precision of measuring or of predicting measurement of length, for instance, if we pay attention not only to centimeters but also to millimeters, microns, angstroms, and so on. And our theories are precise to centimeters, then to millimeters, and so on r…Read more
  •  9
    Review Essays : Phenomenology of Technology (review)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 23 (4): 528-536. 1993.
  • Questions of Science and Metaphysics
    Philosophical Forum 5 (4): 529. 1974.
  •  21
  • Popper on Learning from Experience'
    In Peter Achinstein (ed.), Studies in the philosophy of science, Published By Basil Blackwell With the Cooperation of the University of Pittsburg. pp. 162--71. 1969.
  •  69
    Positive evidence in science and technology
    Philosophy of Science 37 (2): 261-270. 1970.
    If the problem of induction were soluble, it should be solved inductively: by observing how scientists observe, etc. The fact is that scientific research is successful, and the real question is, will it be so in future? If there is a formula of induction by which success is achieved, then by this formula we can say, as long as it will be used science will succeed. If there is no formula it looks as if future success in scientific research is most doubtful. Hence, a transcendental argument for in…Read more
  •  21
  •  2271
    Prescriptions for Responsible Psychiatry
    In William T. O'Donohue & Richard F. Kitchener (eds.), The Philosophy of Psychology, Sage Publications. pp. 339. 1996.
    The ills of psychiatry are currently diagnoses with the aid of deficient etiologies. The currently proposed prescriptions for psychiatry are practically impossible. The defective part of the profession is its leadership which in its very defensiveness sticks to the status quo, thereby owning the worst defects and impeding all possible cure. The current discussions of the matter are pretentious and thus woolly. The minimal requirement from the profession as a whole and from each of its individual…Read more
  •  4
    Priestley's Dissent
    History and Theory 2 45-48. 1963.
  •  41
    Philosophy From a Skeptical Perspective
    with Abraham Meidan
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    One of the questions that philosophers discuss is: How can we avoid, or at least reduce, errors when explaining the world? The skeptical answer to this question is: We cannot avoid errors since no statement is certain or even definitely plausible, but we can eliminate some past errors. This book advocates the skeptical position and discusses its practical applications in science, ethics, aesthetics, and politics. It brings philosophy down to earth and comprises an outline of a skeptical guide to…Read more
  •  145
    On the Reliability of Science: The Critical Rationalist Version
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 43 (1): 100-115. 2013.
    Error and Inference discusses Deborah Mayo’s theory that connects the reliability of science to scientific evidence. She sees it as an essential supplement to the negative principles of critical rationalism. She and Aris Spanos, her co-editor, declare that the discussions in the book amount to tremendous progress. Yet most contributors to the book misconstrue the Socratic character of critical rationalism because they ignore a principal tenet: criticism in and of itself comprises progress, and e…Read more