Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  •  149
    Heidegger made simple (and offensive)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 34 (3): 423-431. 2004.
    presents Heidegger as a devout mystic who viewed the Nazi Party as the sacred vessel of a divine message—even though, the author adds, his religion is secular and so it has no divinity and no immortal soul. Rickey sees him as a utopian. This makes some sense: the unique in the Shoah involves the unique descent of a highly cultured, enlightened nation to the rock bottom of barbarism. Ricky’s text belies his effort to exonerate Heidegger. Key Words: Rickey • Heidegger • secular religion • barbaris…Read more
  •  51
    Dissertation without tears By Joseph Agassi Tel-Aviv University 1. Perfectionism is the loss of the sense of proportion. 2. Perfectionism in education is pedantry and obstruction. 3. Pedantry expels traditional writing techniques. 4. There are many ways to write a scientific study. 5. The best and easiest writing formula is the dialectic. 1. Perfectionism is the loss of the sense of proportion
  •  92
    Induction and stochastic independence
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 41 (1): 141-142. 1990.
  • Il nuovo senso comune
    Nuova Civiltà Delle Macchine 20 (1). 2002.
  •  21
    Imagination and reason
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 453-453. 2007.
    Byrne's book is intended to explain why people imagine the things they do when they create alternatives to reality. Two fruitful areas of further research are: (1) How can her approach explain dreams and daydreams? (2) What is the developmental time course of the child's understanding of reality and imagination?
  •  39
    Ixmann and the gavagai
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 19 (1): 103-116. 1988.
    Dirk Koppelberg is an ambitious new arrival to take notice of. His first book, "Die Aufhebung der analytischen Philosophic: Quine als Synthese von Carnap und Neurath" (Suhrkamp, 1987, pp. 416) is extremely detailed and comprehensive. In succinct 300 pages or so (plus 40 pages of notes and 30 pages of (not too successful) bibliography) he manages to touch on W. V. Quine's diverse concerns, to synthesize them, to relate them to their..
  •  19
    How Technology Aids and Impedes the Growth of Science
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1982. 1982.
    The vision of Horace, combining the sweet and the useful, is an expression of a sense of abundance. It came first and was than supported by Bacon's vision of a science-based technology. Later this was further backed by classical liberalism and by metaphysical progressivism. That technology may impede and even destroy science is obvious. Yet the danger is overlooked--with the aid of the vision of Horace and of neo-conservative (Popperian) politics and of neo-reactionary (Kuhnian) politics of scie…Read more
  •  54
    Gadamer without tears
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 24 (4): 485-505. 1994.
    The chief feature of Gadamer's philosophy is his claim that the humanities obey their own rules concerning reading texts and ensuring certitude. The promise of certitude is illusory, however, and the discourses on interpretation by him and his leading disciples are too confused to instruct the reader. His own sketch of his philosophy, published in his autobiographic Philosophical Apprenticeship, and its reflection in Gadamer and Hermeneutics (Hugh J. Silverman, ed.), shows this and reveals him a…Read more
  •  22
    1. The Real Claim of the Chicago School If anything dramatic has happened in economic theory over the last one hundred years – namely, since the advent of marginalism – then, everyone agrees, it was not the rise of the Chicago neo -classical school which, after all, only synthesized the various versions of marginalism, but the Keynesian Revolution. Assessments of this revolution were repeatedly invited, particularly by opponent, chiefly from Chicago. F. A. von Hayek has explicitly and bitterly b…Read more
  •  18
    Honesty Still Is the Best Policy
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (5): 673-687. 2014.
    Fuller describes the place of intellectuals in the modern world—as researchers, teachers, academics, and citizens. Their job is that of developing and promoting ideas. He explains their failure to perform well and offers advice: say what you think you should say, not necessarily what you think. The advice is unsuitable; it is aimed at advisers and expert witnesses, not at intellectuals. Also, his analysis invites proposals for social reforms aimed at lowering traditional expectations of intellec…Read more
  •  2
    Gasping for Perspective
    Kyiv-Mohyla Humanities Journal 1 243. 2014.
  •  3
    Historical Explanations
    History and Theory 2 74-79. 1963.
  •  45
    From Popper’s Literary Remains
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (3): 552-564. 2010.
    This book is largely unpublished material from Popper’s literary remains regarding his The Open Society and Its Enemies that conveys some interesting stories about its publication and initial reception, throws light on its message, and complements it somewhat. It also contains much that Popper hardly discussed elsewhere
  •  17
    The traditional, dogmatic educational sys tem was reinforced by the addition of science instruction to its curriculum. Three errors are reinforced by this move and the subsequent split of the system into streams. a) Pressure is confused with coercion, b) Interactive study is confused with assigned e x e r c i s e s a n d w i t h s e l f- instruction, and c) Aptitude (disposition) is confused with talent (ability). Reform must begin in the public educational system, at least until experimental sc…Read more
  •  30
    Genius in science
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 5 (2): 145-161. 1975.
  •  55
    How ignoring repeatability leads to magic
    with Nathaniel Laor
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 30 (4): 528-586. 2000.
  •  28
    False prophecy versus true Quest a modest challenge to contemporary relativists
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 22 (3): 285-312. 1992.
    A good theory of rationality should accommodate debates over first principles, such as those of rationality. The modest challenge made in this article is that relativists try to explain the (intellectual) value of some debates about first principles (absolute presuppositions, basic assumptions, intellectual frameworks, intellectual commitments, and paradigms). Relativists claim to justify moving with relative ease from one framework to another, translating chunks of one into the other; this tech…Read more
  •  41
    The symposium on Francesco Guala’s Understanding Institutions was thought provoking. Five critical papers took issue with Guala’s reconciliation of the game-theoretical view of institutions and the rule-governed view. We offer some critical commentary that adopts a different perspective. We agree that institutions are central to social life and, thus, also to the social sciences; they are also prior to and more fundamental than individuals. We add some historical points on the ways previous phil…Read more
  •  23
    Experts within Democracy: The Turner Version
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 45 (3): 370-384. 2015.
    Stephen Turner defends the sociopolitical role that experts—mainly but not only of the scientific kind—play in modern democratic society and explores means for increasing the rationality of their employment. Laudable though this is, at times Turner goes into more detail than democratic principles require; in his enthusiasm for rationality, he aims at levels of adequacy that are not always within the grasp of democracy.
  •  46
    Abstract and Introduction. This essay is an attempt to dispense with the negative aspects of Romanticism and examine whatever positive it has to offer--in the light of ideas scattered through diverse writings of Ernest Gellner
  •  15
    Einstein’s Philosophy Politely Shelved
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 45 (4-5): 515-527. 2015.
    Einstein considered fallibilist methodology obvious and metaphysics the challenging heuristic of physics. This philosophy is a minority view in academic philosophy. Most commentators on Einstein reject it and either refuse to ascribe it to him or declare it an impediment to his researches, his own opinion to the contrary notwithstanding.
  •  2
    Einstein und die Wissenschaftslehre
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 37 (92): 127. 2008.
  • Das Problem der Rationalität in der pluralistischen Gesellschaft
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 28 (71): 251-262. 1994.
  •  47
    Empiricism and inductivism
    Philosophical Studies 14 (6). 1963.