Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  •  22
    Leibniz's Place in the History of Physics
    Journal of the History of Ideas 30 (3): 331. 1969.
  •  22
    Thomas Kuhn, "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions" (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 4 (4): 351. 1966.
  •  22
    Summary and conclusions As a new field, cognitivism began with the total rejection of the old, traditional views of language acquisition and of learning -- individual and collective alike. Chomsky was one of the pioneers in this respect, yet he clouds issues by excessive claim s for his originality and by not allowing the beginner in the art of the acquisition of language the use of learning by making hypotheses and testing them, though he acknowledges that researchers, himself included, do use …Read more
  •  22
    The Politics of Science
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 3 (1): 35-48. 1986.
    ABSTRACT The myth that there is no politics of science is dangerous as it prevents the important and urgently needed institution of some democratic control of the existing system of politics within the commonwealth of learning. Feyerabend's attack on science makes sense only when understood in this way.
  •  22
    1. The Real Claim of the Chicago School If anything dramatic has happened in economic theory over the last one hundred years – namely, since the advent of marginalism – then, everyone agrees, it was not the rise of the Chicago neo -classical school which, after all, only synthesized the various versions of marginalism, but the Keynesian Revolution. Assessments of this revolution were repeatedly invited, particularly by opponent, chiefly from Chicago. F. A. von Hayek has explicitly and bitterly b…Read more
  •  21
    Contemporary European Philosophy, After Half-a-Century (review)
    Polish Journal of Philosophy 5 (1): 139-148. 2011.
  •  21
    Imagination and reason
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30 (5-6): 453-453. 2007.
    Byrne's book is intended to explain why people imagine the things they do when they create alternatives to reality. Two fruitful areas of further research are: (1) How can her approach explain dreams and daydreams? (2) What is the developmental time course of the child's understanding of reality and imagination?
  •  21
    Knowledge and error (review)
    Philosophia 8 (2-3): 485-496. 1978.
  •  21
    Max Planck’s Remorse (review)
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 47 (4-5): 351-358. 2017.
  •  21
  •  21
    The Unity of Hume's Thought
    Hume Studies 1985 (1): 87-109. 1985.
    This is the beginning of an integrated image of Hume's person, thought, and actions as a conservative liberal reformist.
  •  21
    The context of a scientific theory can be epistemological and methodological. Or it car be metaphysical, relating to the intellectual framework within which we cast it. Or it can be intertheoretical, both synchronically and diachronically. My concern here will be mainly diachronical -- the historical context of quantum theory, what is required of it vis -a-vis that context and how well it fulfills this requirement. But I shall come to this only at the later part of this essay. I shall have to cl…Read more
  •  21
  •  20
    This book collects 13 papers that explore Wittgenstein's philosophy throughout the different stages of his career. The author writes from the viewpoint of critical rationalism. The tone of his analysis is friendly and appreciative yet critical. Of these papers, seven are on the background to the philosophy of Wittgenstein. Five papers examine different aspects of it: one on the philosophy of young Wittgenstein, one on his transitional period, and the final three on the philosophy of mature Wittg…Read more
  •  20
    Discussion
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 2 (2): 157-165. 1971.
    No abstract
  •  20
    A Critical Rationalist Aesthetics (edited book)
    with Ian Charles Jarvie
    BRILL. 2008.
    This book is a first attempt to cover the whole area of aesthetics from the point of view of critical rationalism. It takes up and expands upon the more narrowly focused work of E. H. Gombrich, Sheldon Richmond, and Raphael Sassower and Louis Ciccotello. The authors integrate the arts into the scientific world view and acknowledge that there is an aesthetic aspect to anything whatsoever. They pay close attention to the social situatedness of the arts. Their aesthetics treats art as emerging from…Read more
  •  19
    The thesis or theses I wish to present here may, and hopefully should, sound rather trivial. The public role which concerned philosophers should take these days, I suppose, is somewhat similar to the role of preachers in earlier days, namely to state what should be obvious and treated as obvious but is nonetheless systematically overlooked.
  •  19
    Celebrating the open society
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 27 (4): 486-525. 1997.
  •  19
    Book reviews and critical studies (review)
    with John Kekes, Edward Mackinnon, Gerhard D. Wassermann, and Warren Hagar
    Philosophia 10 (1-2): 43-139. 1981.
  •  19
    How Technology Aids and Impedes the Growth of Science
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1982. 1982.
    The vision of Horace, combining the sweet and the useful, is an expression of a sense of abundance. It came first and was than supported by Bacon's vision of a science-based technology. Later this was further backed by classical liberalism and by metaphysical progressivism. That technology may impede and even destroy science is obvious. Yet the danger is overlooked--with the aid of the vision of Horace and of neo-conservative (Popperian) politics and of neo-reactionary (Kuhnian) politics of scie…Read more
  •  19
    Irrationalism Today
    Dialectica 36 (2‐3): 127-146. 1982.
    SummaryAccording to classical rationalism prejudiced people cannot conduct proper research. This is refuted by cases of prejudiced and even Nazi scientists. According to classical rationalism all error is prejudice. This was refuted when crucial experiment between Newton and Einstein favored Einstein. Contemporary popular irrationalists claim crucial experiments are impossible. Their ability to convince rests on the cowardice of the leadership of science which fails to admit openly the present n…Read more
  •  19
    This Message is for You. Maybe
    Philosophy and Literature 7 (1): 95-98. 1983.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:THIS MESSAGE IS FOR YOU. MAYBE. by Joseph Agassi There is a mood often enough conjured in science fiction literature to be familiar to every fan, the mood of seemingly intentional yet probably remdom contact between two individuals across immense space-time expanses. The hero of a complicated chase story has lost contact with the mother planet, has long ago leuided on a strange pleuiet, emd there, right now, just walking across the p…Read more
  •  18
    Honesty Still Is the Best Policy
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (5): 673-687. 2014.
    Fuller describes the place of intellectuals in the modern world—as researchers, teachers, academics, and citizens. Their job is that of developing and promoting ideas. He explains their failure to perform well and offers advice: say what you think you should say, not necessarily what you think. The advice is unsuitable; it is aimed at advisers and expert witnesses, not at intellectuals. Also, his analysis invites proposals for social reforms aimed at lowering traditional expectations of intellec…Read more
  •  18
    This book succeeds in being nice all round. Its means are slight distortions of issues in dispute. A preferable approach would be to inform readers of the sharp rifts in the field and their ramifications and then to challenge beginners to think about how to deal with the situation.
  •  18
    The novelty of Chomsky's theories
    In David Martel Johnson & Christina E. Erneling (eds.), The Future of the Cognitive Revolution, Oxford University Press. pp. 136--148. 1997.