Joseph Agassi

York University
D'Annunzio University of Chieti–Pescara
  •  46
    Introducing Philosophy of Social Science
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 44 (4): 536-550. 2014.
    This book succeeds in being nice all round. Its means are slight distortions of issues in dispute. A preferable approach would be to inform readers of the sharp rifts in the field and their ramifications and then to challenge beginners to think about how to deal with the situation
  •  45
    From Popper’s Literary Remains
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 40 (3): 552-564. 2010.
    This book is largely unpublished material from Popper’s literary remains regarding his The Open Society and Its Enemies that conveys some interesting stories about its publication and initial reception, throws light on its message, and complements it somewhat. It also contains much that Popper hardly discussed elsewhere
  •  45
    Back to the drawing board
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 35 (4): 509-518. 2005.
    Within ontology new theories are extremely rare. Hacking bravely claims to have one: "historical ontology" or "dynamic nominalism." Regrettably, he uses "nominalism" idiosyncratically, without explaining it or its qualifier. He does say what historical ontology is: it is "the presentation of the history of ontology in context." This idea is laudable, as it invites presenting idealism as once attractive but no longer so (due to changes in perception theory, for example). But this idea is a propos…Read more
  •  44
    On September 17, 1994, Karl Popper died at the age of 92.He was described as the official opposition of the “ Vienna Circle”, the philosophical club which in the inter-war period was glamorous and which espoused the then popular doctrine of logical positivism, so-called. His relations with that club were friendly-hostile, to use the term with which he liked to characterize the relations between scientific researchers. He is the last of that generation (unless it is Carl G. Hempel, who, however, …Read more
  •  44
    Dinosaurs and horses, or: Ways with nature
    with Robert S. Cohen
    Synthese 32 (1-2). 1975.
  •  44
    Analogies as generalizations
    Philosophy of Science 31 (4): 351-356. 1964.
    Analogies have been traditionally recognized as a proper part of inductive procedures, akin to generalizations. Seldom, however, have they been presented as superior to generalizations, in the attainability of a higher degree of certitude for their conclusions or in other respects. Though Bacon definitely preferred analogy to generalization, the tradition seems to me to go the other way—until the recent publication of works by Mary B. Hesse and, perhaps, R. Harré.
  •  43
    The Problem of Analytic Philosophy
    with Ian C. Jarvie
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (5): 413-433. 2019.
    Dainton and Robinson’s Companion traces lines of descent of analytic philosophy from ancestors. They characterize analytic philosophy as a movement, a tradition, a style, and a commitment to the va...
  •  42
    Philosophy From a Skeptical Perspective
    with Abraham Meidan
    Cambridge University Press. 2008.
    One of the questions that philosophers discuss is: How can we avoid, or at least reduce, errors when explaining the world? The skeptical answer to this question is: We cannot avoid errors since no statement is certain or even definitely plausible, but we can eliminate some past errors. This book advocates the skeptical position and discusses its practical applications in science, ethics, aesthetics, and politics. It brings philosophy down to earth and comprises an outline of a skeptical guide to…Read more
  •  41
    To Dismiss "The Received View"
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 42 (3): 449-456. 2012.
    This volume is a historical anthology of interesting views on science from antiquity to the twentieth century plus a defensive anthology of logical positivism, whose legacy deserves better: clear-eyed assessment and then putting to rest
  •  41
    Precision in theory and in measurement
    Philosophy of Science 35 (3): 287-290. 1968.
    An intuitive idea concerning degrees of precision is widely accepted, and it is that we increase precision of theories by paying attention to ever decreasing orders of magnitude of measurements which we incorporate in these theories. We increase precision of measuring or of predicting measurement of length, for instance, if we pay attention not only to centimeters but also to millimeters, microns, angstroms, and so on. And our theories are precise to centimeters, then to millimeters, and so on r…Read more
  •  40
    Popper and the establishment
    with Nimrod Bar-Am
    Critical Review: A Journal of Politics and Society 17 (1-2): 13-23. 2005.
    The central thesis of Karl Popper's philosophy is that intellectual and political progress are best achieved by not deferring to dogmatic authority. His philosophy of science is a plea for the replacement of classic dogmatic methodology with critical debate. His philosophy of politics, similarly, is a plea for replacing Utopian social and political engineering with a more fallibilist, piecemeal variety. Many confuse his anti‐dogmatism with relativism, and his anti‐authoritarianism with Cold War …Read more
  •  40
    Popper and His Popular Critics: Thomas Kuhn, Paul Feyerabend and Imre Lakatos: Appendix
    Epistemology and Philosophy of Science 59 (4): 181-188. 2022.
    Popper’s popular critics – Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Lakatos – replace his older, Wittgenstein-style critics, now defunct. His new critics played with the idea of criticism as beneficial, in vain search of variants of these that could better appeal to the public. Some of their criticism of Popper is valid but marginal for the dispute about rationality. He was Fallibilist; they hedged about it. He viewed learning from experience as learning from error; they were unclear about it. His view resembles F…Read more
  •  40
    Toward a Fictionless Liberalism
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 46 (1): 77-91. 2016.
    This Companion centers on the fictitious social contract that can be used to justify liberalism. As justification, the theory of the contract either fully justifies a regime as liberal or it fully condemns it as illiberal. This conflicts with the common recognition that liberalism is a matter of degree. John Rawls is taken as the leading light; yet at best the Companion manages to picture him as well-intended but hopelessly confusing.
  •  40
    The Future of Berkeley’s Instrumentalism
    International Studies in Philosophy 7 167-178. 1975.
  •  39
    Ixmann and the gavagai
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 19 (1): 103-116. 1988.
    Dirk Koppelberg is an ambitious new arrival to take notice of. His first book, "Die Aufhebung der analytischen Philosophic: Quine als Synthese von Carnap und Neurath" (Suhrkamp, 1987, pp. 416) is extremely detailed and comprehensive. In succinct 300 pages or so (plus 40 pages of notes and 30 pages of (not too successful) bibliography) he manages to touch on W. V. Quine's diverse concerns, to synthesize them, to relate them to their..
  •  39
    The symposium on Francesco Guala’s Understanding Institutions was thought provoking. Five critical papers took issue with Guala’s reconciliation of the game-theoretical view of institutions and the rule-governed view. We offer some critical commentary that adopts a different perspective. We agree that institutions are central to social life and, thus, also to the social sciences; they are also prior to and more fundamental than individuals. We add some historical points on the ways previous phil…Read more
  •  39
    The death of heuristic?
    with Peggy Marchi and John R. Wettersten
    Philosophia 11 (3-4): 249-276. 1982.
  •  38
    Comments and replies
    with Paul K. Feyerabend
    Philosophia 6 (1): 177-191. 1976.
  •  38
    Wissenschaft und Metaphysik
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 9 (1): 97-106. 1979.
    The erroneous hostility to metaphysics is justified by the clashes between science and metaphysics plus the inability to allow clashes within science. The defenders of metaphysics as world-views offering intellectual frameworks for science have overlooked this fact. Einstein and Popper have legitimized the inclusion of clashes well within the domain of science. This resolves the difficulty of the allegiance to both. Science offers testable explanations and metaphysics comprehension; both are ins…Read more
  •  38
    Both a Popper biography and an autobiography, Agassi's "A Philosopher's Apprentice" tells the riveting story of his intellectual formation in 1950s London, a young brilliant philosopher struggling with an intellectual giant - father, mentor, and rival, all at the same time. His subsequent rebellion and declaration of independence leads to a painful break, never to be completely healed. No other writer has Agassi's psychological insight into Popper, and no other book captures like this one the in…Read more
  •  37
    Knowledge personal or social
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 28 (4): 522-551. 1998.
    Karl Popper's methodology can be seen as the situational logic of research. Popper called his method "Epistemology without a Knowing Subject." It was dismissed as metaphysical by those who refuse to give up an ideal knowing subject (a perfect human inductive processor). This article surveys the failure of modem discussions of this ideal, from the earliest (the writings of Sir Francis Bacon) to the latest (Kripke). The knowing subject exits at last, but leaves behind interesting results. The idea…Read more
  •  37
    Global Responsibility
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 7 (2): 217-221. 1990.
    ABSTRACT Concern with global responsibility for survival as such invites the creation of a specific international organization. The new body should adjudicate as to which disputes are open (such as, for example, concerning the advisability of building nuclear plants) and which are not (for example, white supremacy); most significantly, the new body should carefully guard its credibility by sticking to veracity, by avoiding deceit even in extreme situations. In particular it behoves us all to con…Read more
  •  37
    The system of higher education always has a significant place in national political affairs. Politically indifferent academics may legitimately ignore this. Those concerned with the welfare of the system of higher education, however, cannot afford this luxury. Further, intellectuals, including academics, are a significant political factor even when passive. Even were all of them to ignore all politics, including the ever-present political importance of the educational system for national politic…Read more
  •  36
    No more discovery in physics? (review)
    Synthese 18 (1): 103-108. 1968.
  •  36
    Stegmüller squared
    with John R. Wettersten
    Zeitschrift Für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 11 (1): 86-94. 1980.
    Wolfgang Stegmüller, the leading German philosopher of science, considers the status of scientific revolutions the central issue in the field ever since "the famous Popper-Lakatos-Kuhn discussion" of a decade and a half ago, comments on "almost all contributions to this problem", and offers his alternative solutions in a series of papers culminating with, and summarized in, his recent "A Combined Approach to Dynamics of Theories. How To Improve Historical Interpretations of Theory Change By Appl…Read more
  •  36
    Summary of AFOS workshop, 1994
    Foundations of Science 1 (1): 161-166. 1995.
  •  36
    Rationality: A comment on Raymond Boudon's paper
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 7 (1). 1993.
  •  35
    I. God save us from our friends; enemies we have no more
    Philosophia 16 (2): 209-238. 1986.
  •  35
    Newell's list
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 26 (5): 601-602. 2003.
    Newell wanted a theory of cognition to abide by some explicit criteria, here called the Newell Test. The test differs from the Turing Test because it is explicit. The Newell Test will include the Turing Test if its characterization of cognition is complete. It is not. Its use here is open-ended: A system that does not pass it well invites improvement.