•  66
    What are Concepts?
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 39 (96). 2010.
  •  2
    Necessity and normativity
    In Hans D. Sluga & David G. Stern (eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Wittgenstein, Cambridge University Press. pp. 198--225. 1996.
  •  4
    Dictionnaire Wittgenstein
    Editions Gallimard. 2003.
    Ce dictionnaire apporte à l'œuvre de Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951) ce qui était à ses yeux la chose la plus importante en philosophie, une " vue synoptique ". L'œuvre de Wittgenstein, par son style et son inachèvement, demande beaucoup au lecteur. Ce livre est un véritable guide, dressant la carte de sa philosophie, ou plutôt de ses philosophies, puisque Wittgenstein présente le cas unique d'un grand philosophe auteur de deux philosophies, également influentes, et dont la seconde est largement…Read more
  •  172
    Thought, language, and animals
    In Abraham Zvie Bar-On (ed.), Grazer Philosophische Studien, Distributed in the U.s.a. By Humanities Press. pp. 139-160. 1986.
    This paper discusses Wittgenstein's ideas about the relation between thought, neurophysiology and language, and about the mental capacities of non-linguistic animals. It deals with his initial espousal and later rejection of a 'language of thought', his arguments against the idea that thought requires a medium of images or words, his reasons for resisting the encephalocentric conception of the mind which dominates contemporary philosophy of mind, his mature views about the connection between tho…Read more
  •  1
    Concepts: Between the Subjective and the Objective
    In John Cottingham & Peter Hacker (eds.), Mind, Method, and Morality: Essays in Honour of Anthony Kenny, Oxford University Press. 2010.
  • Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein: Language as Representation and Will
    In Christopher Janaway (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer, Cambridge University Press. pp. 422--458. 1999.
  •  78
    A radical interpretation of Davidson: Reply to Alvarez
    Philosophical Quarterly 45 (179): 206-212. 1995.
    The paper is a reply to the accusation ("Philosophical Quarterly", 44, 1994) that my The Indispensability of Translation' ("Philosophical Quartrely", 43, 1993) misrepresents Davidson's account of radical interpretation. It defends my claim that Davidson assimilates everyday understanding to the interpretation of an alien language, and discusses the ways in which he identifies interpretation with translation. I admit that Davidson has recently acknowledged first person authority concerning speake…Read more
  •  92
    My paper reflects on the debate about reasons for action and action explanations between Wittgensteinian teleological approaches and causalist theories inspired by Davidson. After a brief discussion of similarities and differences in the philosophy of language, I sketch the prehistory and history of the controversy. I show that the conflict between Wittgenstein and Davidson revolves neither around revisionism nor around naturalism. Even in the philosophy of mind and action, Davidson is not as re…Read more
  •  85
    Wittgenstein and Quine (edited book)
    with Robert L. Arrington
    Routledge. 1996.
    This unique study brings together for the first time two of the most important philosophers of this century. Never before have these two thinkers been compared - and commentators' opinions on their relationship differ greatly. Are the views of Wittgenstein and Quine on method and the nature of philosophy comparable or radically opposed? Does Wittgenstein's concept of language engender that of Quine, or threaten its philosophical foundations? An understanding of the similarities and differences b…Read more
  •  14
    Vygotsky and mead on the self, meaning and internalisation
    Studies in Soviet Thought 31 (2): 131-148. 1986.
  •  132
    Meaning and rule following
    with James D. Wright
    In Hans-Johann Glock & James D. Wright (eds.), , . pp. 841-849. 2015.
    According to a venerable tradition in philosophy and linguistics, expressions have meaning through being subject to conventions or rules. This claim has become a central topic of contemporary philosophy of language and mind in the wake of Wittgenstein and Kripke, largely because the normativity of meaning is regarded as a serious challenge to naturalism. One reaction to this challenge is to deny that the normativity of meaning is genuine. While there are ‘semantic principles’ specifying conditio…Read more
  •  200
    Doing Good by Splitting Hairs? Analytic Philosophy and Applied Ethics
    Journal of Applied Philosophy 28 (3): 225-240. 2011.
    This article explores the connections between analytic philosophy and applied ethics — both historical and substantive. Historically speaking, applied ethics is a child of analytic philosophy. It arose as the result of two factors in the 1960s: the re-emergence of normative ethics on the one hand, and urgent social and political challenges on the other. But is there a significant substantive link between applied ethics and analytic philosophy? I argue that applied ethics inherited important ‘ana…Read more
  •  48
  •  190
    Can Animals Act For Reasons?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 52 (3): 232-254. 2009.
    This essay argues that non-linguistic animals qualify not just for externalist notions of rationality (maximizing biological fitness or utility), but also for internal ones. They can act for reasons in several senses: their behaviour is subject to intentional explanations, they can act in the light of reasons - provided that the latter are conceived as objective facts rather than subjective mental states - and they can deliberate. Finally, even if they could not, it would still be misguided to m…Read more
  •  5
    Replies to my commentators
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 30 (1): 115-144. 2011.
  •  102
    Animal Minds: A Non-Representationalist Approach
    American Philosophical Quarterly 50 (3): 213-232. 2013.
    Do animals have minds? We have known at least since Aristotle that humans constitute one species of animal. And some benighted contemporaries apart, we also know that most humans have minds. To have any bite, therefore, the question must be restricted to non-human animals, to which I shall henceforth refer simply as "animals." I shall further assume that animals are bereft of linguistic faculties. So, do some animals have minds comparable to those of humans? As regards that question, there are t…Read more
  •  148
    Quine and Davidson on Language, Thought and Reality
    Cambridge University Press. 2003.
    Quine and Davidson are among the leading thinkers of the twentieth century. Their influence on contemporary philosophy is second to none, and their impact is also strongly felt in disciplines such as linguistics and psychology. This book is devoted to both of them, but also questions some of their basic assumptions. Hans-Johann Glock critically scrutinizes their ideas on ontology, truth, necessity, meaning and interpretation, thought and language, and shows that their attempts to accommodate mea…Read more
  •  30
  •  156
    From armchair to reality?
    Ratio 23 (3): 339-348. 2010.
  •  182
    The linguistic doctrine revisited
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 66 (1): 143-170. 2003.
    At present, there is an almost universal consensus that the linguistic doctrine of logical necessity is grotesque. This paper explores avenues for rehabilitating a limited version of the doctrine, according to which the special status of analytic statements like 'All vixens are female' is to be explained by reference to language. Far from being grotesque, this appeal to language has a respectable philosophical pedigree and chimes with common sense, as Quine came to realize. The problem lies in d…Read more
  •  308
    Concepts, conceptual schemes and grammar
    Philosophia 37 (4): 653-668. 2009.
    This paper considers the connection between concepts, conceptual schemes and grammar in Wittgenstein’s last writings. It lists eight claims about concepts that one can garner from these writings. It then focuses on one of them, namely that there is an important difference between conceptual and factual problems and investigations. That claim draws in its wake other claims, all of them revolving around the idea of a conceptual scheme, what Wittgenstein calls a ‘grammar’. I explain why Wittgenstei…Read more
  •  61
    Subjective, intersubjective, objective
    Philosophical Investigations 26 (4). 2003.
    Books reviewed: Donald Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective.
  •  87
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 0, Issue 0, Page 1-5, Ahead of Print.
  •  44
    Wie wichtig ist Erkenntnistheorie?
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 56 (1). 2002.
    In der zeitgenössischen analytischen Philosophe wird oft behauptet, die Erkenntnistheorie sei weniger fundamental als die Ontologie, da sich aus Aussagen über unser Erkenntnisvermögen keine Aussagen über die Wirklichkeit ableiten lassen und die Frage nach der Beschaffenheit der Wirklichkeit der Frage nach ihrer Erkennbarkeit vorausgeht. Dagegen verteidige ich folgende Thesen: eine Form der Erkenntnistheorie—die Auseinandersetzung mit der Skepsis —ist nicht fundamental; eine andere Form—die Ausei…Read more
  •  20
    Wittgenstein's `Philosophical Investigations': Text and Context
    with Robert L. Arrington
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (176): 392-394. 1994.