•  61
    Subjective, intersubjective, objective
    Philosophical Investigations 26 (4). 2003.
    Books reviewed: Donald Davidson, Subjective, Intersubjective, Objective.
  •  60
    Vygotsky and mead on the self, meaning and internalisation
    Studies in East European Thought 31 (2): 131-148. 1986.
  •  57
    Th ere is a growing feeling that analytic philosophy is in crisis. At the same time there is a widespread and prima facie attractive conception of analytic philosophy which implies that it equates to good philosophy. In recognition of these confl icting tendencies, my paper raises the question of whether anything could be wrong with analytic philosophy. In section 1 I indicate why analytic philosophy cannot be defi ned by reference to geography, topics, doctrines or even methods. Th is leaves op…Read more
  •  56
    Thought, judgment and perception
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 86 (1): 207-221. 2012.
  •  51
    Animal minds
    In Glock Hans Johann (ed.), , . 2001.
  •  51
    Norms, Reasons, and Anthropological Naturalism
    Philosophical Topics 50 (1): 9-32. 2022.
    This article addresses the two most important areas of potential conflict between inferentialism and naturalism, namely normativity and rationality. Concerning the first, it sides with inferentialism, while at the same time developing a normativist position less vulnerable to naturalistic objections. There is nothing problematic or mysterious about semantic normativity or normativity in general. But one needs to distinguish different types of normativity and recognize that statements of norms ca…Read more
  •  50
    Relativism and radical interpretation
    The European Legacy 2 (4): 603-608. 1997.
    It has been argued by a number of philosophers that relativism of rationality and truth is inconsistent with the preconditions for radical interpretation of speech. For radical interpretation involves the imposition of certain universal standards of rationality and truth upon the material to be interpreted. Hence an anti-Relativist argument ensues. Against this, I argue that the principles of radical interpretation leave sufficient slack for relativism of a non-Trivial sort to creep in
  •  50
    Notions of arbitrariness
    Mind and Language 38 (4): 1120-1137. 2022.
    Arbitrariness is a distinctive feature of human language, and a growing body of comparative work is investigating its presence in animal communication. But what is arbitrariness, exactly? We propose to distinguish four notions of semiotic arbitrariness: a notion of opaque association between sign forms and semiotic functions, one of sign‐function mapping optionality, one of acquisition‐dependent sign‐function coupling, and one of lack of motivatedness. We characterize these notions, illustrate t…Read more
  •  50
    Zurich
    The Philosophers' Magazine 56 (56): 47-50. 2012.
  •  50
    Précis of What is Analytic Philosophy?
    Teorema: International Journal of Philosophy 30 (1). 2011.
  •  48
  •  47
    Neo-Kantianism and Analytic Philosophy
    In Nicolas De Warren & Andrea Staiti (eds.), New Approaches to Neo-Kantianism, Cambridge University Press. pp. 25-41. 2015.
  •  46
    Truth without People?
    Philosophy 72 (279). 1997.
    There is a venerable tradition according to which the concept of truth is totally independent of human beings, their actions and beliefs, because truth consists in the correspondence of mind-independentpropositions to a mind-independent reality. For want of arespect. One way of doing so is relativism, the idea that whether a belief is true or false depends on the point of view of individuals or communities. A closely related position is a consensus theory of truth, according to which a belief is…Read more
  •  46
    Determinacy of Content
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 27 101-120. 2020.
    Few arguments against intentional states in animals have stood the test of time. But one objection by Stich and Davidson has never been rebutted. In my reconstruction it runs: Ascribing beliefs to animals is vacuous, unless something counts as an animal believing one specific “content” rather than another; Nothing counts as an animal believing one specific content rather than another, because of their lack of language; Ergo: Ascribing beliefs to animals is vacuous. Several attempts to block the …Read more
  •  46
    What Is Meaning? A Wittgensteinian Answer to an Un-Wittgensteinian Question
    In James Conant & Sebastian Sunday (eds.), Wittgenstein on Philosophy, Objectivity, and Meaning, Cambridge University Press. pp. 185-210. 2019.
    Wittgenstein has often been ascribed a ‘use-theory of meaning’. However, he explicitly renounced theory construction. Furthermore, his slogan ‘Don’t ask for the meaning, ask for the use!’ invites circumventing the question ‘What is meaning?’ altogether. This chapter argues that, Wittgenstein’s ambivalence notwithstanding, there is no merit in avoiding the title question (‘What is meaning?’). Moreover, it is argued that, while Wittgenstein’s reflections are incompatible with a formal theory of me…Read more
  •  44
    Wie wichtig ist Erkenntnistheorie?
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 56 (1). 2002.
    In der zeitgenössischen analytischen Philosophe wird oft behauptet, die Erkenntnistheorie sei weniger fundamental als die Ontologie, da sich aus Aussagen über unser Erkenntnisvermögen keine Aussagen über die Wirklichkeit ableiten lassen und die Frage nach der Beschaffenheit der Wirklichkeit der Frage nach ihrer Erkennbarkeit vorausgeht. Dagegen verteidige ich folgende Thesen: eine Form der Erkenntnistheorie—die Auseinandersetzung mit der Skepsis —ist nicht fundamental; eine andere Form—die Ausei…Read more
  •  44
    Abusing Use1
    Dialectica 50 (3): 205-224. 1996.
    summaryThis paper discusses objections against the idea that the meaning of a word is its use. Sct. 1 accepts Rundle's point that ‘meaning’ and ‘use’ are used differently, but insists that this is compatible with holding that use determines meaning, an therefore holds the key to conceptual analysis. Scts. 2–4 rebut three lines of argument which claim that linguistic philosophy goes astray by reading into the meaning of words non‐semantic features of its use: Searle's general speech act fallacy c…Read more
  •  42
    This chapter explores whether a version of causalism about reasons for action can be saved by giving up Davidsonian psychologism and endorsing objectivism, so that the reasons for which we act are the normative reasons that cause our corresponding actions. We address two problems for ‘objecto-causalism’, actions for merely apparent normative reasons and actions performed in response to future normative reasons—in neither of these cases can the reason for which the agent acts cause her action. To…Read more
  •  41
    A Wittgenstein Dictionary
    Wiley-Blackwell. 1996.
    This lucid and accessible dictionary presents technical terms that Wittgenstein introduced into philosophical debate or transformed substantially, and also topics to which he made a substantial contribution. Hans-Johann Glock places Wittgenstein's ideas in their relevance to current debates. The entries delineate Wittgenstein's lines of argument on particular issues, assessing their strengths and weaknesses, and shed light on fundamental exegetical controversies. The dictionary entries are prefa…Read more