•  43
    Kinds of kinds: Individuality and biological species
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 3 (2). 1989.
  •  43
    Love: A Very Short Introduction
    Oxford University Press. 2015.
    Do we love someone for their virtue, their beauty, or their moral or other qualities? Are love's characteristic desires altruistic or selfish? Are there duties of love? What do the sciences tell us about love? In this Very Short Introduction, Ronald de Sousa explores the different kinds of love, from affections to romantic love.
  •  42
    Seizing the Hedgehog by the Tail: Taylor on the Self and Agency
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 18 (3): 421-432. 1988.
    For those of us who are sympathetic to the research program of cognitive science, it is especially useful to face the deepest and sharpest critic of that program. Charles Taylor, who defines himself as a ‘hedgehog’ whose ‘single rather tightly related agenda’ fits into a very ancient and rather elusive debate between naturalism and anti-naturalism, may well be that critic. My ambition in this paper is to distill Taylor’s central objection to the cognitive science approach to agency and the self …Read more
  •  41
    Perversion and Death
    The Monist 86 (1): 90-114. 2003.
    Philosophers like to warn against fools’ paradises: not places where fools can safely cavort, but rather conditions in which fools mistakenly think themselves happy. The warning presupposes that real and merely apparent happiness can be told apart. Of course that claim is not altogether disinterested, since philosophers have a professional investment in the distinction. Thus they have endorsed this or that attitude to death, holding up promises of ultimate comfort or threats of excruciating regr…Read more
  •  38
    Emotional Truth
    Oxford University Press USA. 2011.
    The word "truth" retains, in common use, traces of origins that link it to trust, truth, and truce, connoting ideas of fidelity, loyalty, and authenticity. The word has become, in contemporary philosophy, encased in a web of technicalities, but we know that a true image is a faithful portrait; a true friend a loyal one. In a novel or a poem, too, we have a feel for what is emotionally true, though we are not concerned with the actuality of events and characters depicted. To have emotions is to c…Read more
  •  36
    Emotions, Education and Time
    Metaphilosophy 21 (4): 434-446. 1990.
  •  35
    Comment: Language and Dimensionality in Appraisal Theory
    Emotion Review 5 (2): 171-175. 2013.
    The proliferation of dimensions of appraisal is both welcome and worrying. The preoccupation with sorting out causes may be somewhat otiose. And the ubiquity of emotions in levels of processing raises intriguing problems about the role of language in identifying and triggering emotions and appraisals
  •  33
    The Natural Shiftiness of Natural Kinds
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (4): 561-580. 1984.
    The Philosophical search for Natural Kinds is motivated by the hope of finding ontological categories that are independent of our interests. Other requirements, of varying importance, are commonly made of kinds that claim to be natural. But no such categories are to be found. Virtually any kind can be termed ‘natural’ relative to some set of interests and epistemic priorities. Science determines those priorities at any particular stage of its progress, and what kinds are most ‘natural’ in that s…Read more
  •  33
    Why think?: evolution and the rational mind
    Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Introduction -- Function and destiny -- What's the good of thinking? -- Rationality, individual and collective -- Irrationality.
  •  27
    The politics of mental illness
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 15 (1-4): 187-202. 1972.
  •  27
    In the following comments, I will raise no major objection to Furtak’s main line of argument. My questions are essentially requests for clarification. They focus on three key expressions: first, the “unified” character of emotional agitation and intentionality; second, the unique “mode of cognition” claimed for emotions; and third, the “emotional a priori.”
  •  25
    Les émotions contemplatives et l’objectivité des valeurs
    Philosophiques 45 (2): 499-505. 2018.
    Ronald de Sousa
  •  25
    Divided Minds and Successive Selves (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 60 (2): 492-495. 2000.
    This book's dedication reads “to the man I married.” The phrase is a nice incitement to reflect on the book's topic: is the man she married identical with her present husband? Does the dedication imply a subtle reproach? a note of resignation before the inevitable fact that the man I married cannot be the one I'm married to? By the end of her book, Radden concludes that we can't get away from “normative demands of individuality” that remain anchored to common sense. The challenge she takes up is…Read more
  •  24
    Individual natures
    Philosophia 26 (1-2): 3-21. 1998.
  •  22
    Emotion Review, Volume 14, Issue 4, Page 257-261, October 2022. Müller argues that the perceptual or “Axiological Receptivity” model of emotions is incoherent, because it requires an emotion to apprehend and respond to its formal object at the same time. He defends a contrasting view of emotions as “Position-Takings" towards “formal objects”, aspects of an emotion's target pertinent to the subject's concerns. I first cast doubt on the cogency of Müller's attack on AR as begging questions about t…Read more
  •  22
    Individualism and Local Control
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 20 (sup1): 185-205. 1994.
    In both biology and psychology, the notion of an individual is indispensable yet puzzling. It has played a variety of roles in diverse contexts, ranging from philosophical problems of personal identity to scientific questions about the immunological mechanisms for telling ‘self’ from ‘non-self.’ There are notorious cases in which the question of individuality is difficult to settle — ant hill, slime mold, or beehive, for instance. Yet the notion of an individual organism, both dependent on and i…Read more
  •  19
    The Structure of Emotions
    Noûs 25 (3): 367-373. 1991.
  •  18
    Does the eye know calculus? The threshold of representation in classical and connectionist models
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 5 (2). 1991.
    Abstract The notion of representation lies at the crossroads of questions about the nature of belief and knowledge, meaning, and intentionality. But there is some hope that it might be simpler than all those. If we could understand it clearly, it might then help to explicate those more difficult notions. In this paper, my central aim is to find a principled criterion, along lines that make biological sense, for deciding just when it becomes theoretically plausible to ascribe to some process or s…Read more
  •  18
    What Philosophy Contributes to Emotion Science
    Philosophies 7 (4): 87. 2022.
    Contemporary philosophers have paid increasing attention to the empirical research on emotions that has blossomed in many areas of the social sciences. In this paper, I first sketch the common roots of science and philosophy in Ancient Greek thought. I illustrate the way that specific empirical sciences can be regarded as branching out from a central trunk of philosophical speculation. On the basis of seven informal characterizations of what is distinctive about philosophical thinking, I then dr…Read more
  •  17
    L'erotisme
    In Julien A. Deonna & Emma Tieffenbach (eds.), Petit Traité des Valeurs, Edition D’ithaque. pp. 132-139. 2018.
  •  17
    A Third Front in Philosophy
    Common Knowledge 20 (2): 223-234. 2014.
    In a colloquium on “lyric philosophy,” this contribution records the efforts of an analytic philosopher to come to grips with questions that Jan Zwicky, who is both a fine poet and a subtle philosopher, has raised about anglophone analytic philosophy. The essay situates Zwicky between the analytic and Continental traditions in philosophy: like the best analytic philosophers, it is argued, she is enamored of clarity, but, like what is best in the Continental tradition, she demands of philosophy a…Read more
  •  15
    Applying Sociobiology (review)
    Biology and Philosophy 7 (2): 237. 1992.
  •  14
    Paradoxical Emotion: On sui generis Emotional Irrationality
    In Sarah Stroud & Christine Tappolet (eds.), Weakness of will and practical irrationality, Oxford University Press. 2003.
    Weakness of will violates practical rationality; but may also be viewed as an epistemic failing. Conflicts between strategic and epistemic rationality suggest that we need a superordinate standard to arbitrate between them. Contends that such a standard is to be found at the axiological level, apprehended by emotions. Axiological rationality is sui generis, reducible to neither the strategic nor the epistemic. But, emotions are themselves capable of raising paradoxes and antinomies, particularly…Read more