•  3164
    An Argument Against Cloning
    with Jaime Ahlberg and Harry Brighouse
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (4): 539-566. 2010.
    It is technically possible to clone a human being. The result of the procedure would be a human being in its own right. Given the current level of cloning technology concerning other animals there is every reason to believe that early human clones will have shorter-than-average life-spans, and will be unusually prone to disease. In addition, they would be unusually at risk of genetic defects, though they would still, probably, have lives worth living. But with experimentation and experience, ser…Read more
  •  66
    Justice is the first virtue of social institutions, and of the institutions which regulate schooling no less than others. Education policy, just like social policy more generally, should be guided principally by considerations of justice and only secondarily by pragmatic considerations such as what compromises must be made with existing social forces opposed to justice in order to optimize the justice of the existing institutions. But of course, in an otherwise unjust society there are sharp lim…Read more
  •  3
    No Title available: REVIEWS
    Economics and Philosophy 10 (1): 127-133. 1994.
  •  40
    Complex Egalitarianism: A Review of Alex Callinicos 'Equality' (review)
    with Erik Olin Wright
    Historical Materialism 10 (1): 193-222. 2001.
  •  6
    Is There Any Such Thing as Political Liberalism?
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 75 (3-4): 318-332. 2017.
  •  20
    What’s Wrong With Privatising Schools?
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 38 (4): 617-631. 2004.
    Full privatisation of schools would involve states abstaining from providing, funding or regulating schools. I argue that full privatisation would, in most circumstances, worsen social injustice in schooling. I respond to James Tooley’s critique of my own arguments for funding and regulation and markets. I argue that even his principle of educational adequacy requires a certain level of state involvement and demonstrate that his arguments against a principle of educational equality fail. I show,…Read more
  •  52
    Against Nationalism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume 22 365-405. 1996.
    A recent resurgence of interest within analytical political philosophy in the status of ethnic and national minorities coincides with the re-emergence of national identity as a primary organizing principle of political conflict, and with an increasing attentiveness to identity and recognition as organizing principles of political struggle. The recent theoretical literature within political philosophy has focused very much on recognizing the importance of national identity, and allowing attention…Read more
  •  72
    Political equality in justice as fairness
    Philosophical Studies 86 (2): 155-184. 1997.
  •  1775
    Legitimate parental partiality
    Philosophy and Public Affairs 37 (1): 43-80. 2008.
    Some of the barriers to the realisation of equality reflect the value of respecting prerogatives people have to favour themselves. Even G.A. Cohen, whose egalitarianism is especially pervasive and demanding, says that
  •  41
    In defence of educational equality
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 29 (3). 1995.
    The principle of educational equality is important for the plausibility of egalitarianism. I argue against John Wilson's recent attempts to show that two particular versions of the principle are incoherent, and I rebut his argument that even if it were coherent it would be wrong to endorse it. Two other objections to this version of the principle are considered and shown not to be decisive. The principle governing the distribution of educational resources that Wilson advocates is also rejected.
  •  68
    Can Justice as Fairness Accommodate the Disabled?
    Social Theory and Practice 27 (4): 537-560. 2001.
  •  535
    What rights (if any) do children have
    In David Archard & Colin M. Macleod (eds.), The Moral and Political Status of Children, Oxford University Press. pp. 31--52. 2002.
    According to the interest theory of rights, the primary function of rights is the protection of fundamental interests. Since children undeniably have fundamental interests that merit protection, it is perfectly sensible to attribute rights, especially welfare rights, to them. The interest theory need not be hostile to the accommodation of rights that protect agency because, at least in the case of adults, there is a strong connection between the protection of agency and the promotion of welfare.…Read more
  •  32
    A modest defence of school choice
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 36 (4). 2002.
    This is a response to Samara Foster’s engaging critique of my book School Choice and Social Justice. In this response to her criticisms I clarify and try to correct some apparent misunderstandings of the book, but also take the opportunity to pose again a challenge to opponents of choice which neither she, nor other of my critics, has taken up.
  •  88
    School Choice and Social Justice
    British Journal of Educational Studies 50 (3): 402-403. 2002.
    Defends a theory of social justice for education from within an egalitarian version of liberalism. The theory involves a strong commitment to educational equality, and to the idea that children's rights include a right to personal autonomy. The book argues that school reform must always be evaluated from the perspective of social justice and applies the theory, in particular, to school choice proposals. It looks at the parental choice schemes in Milwaukee, Wisconsin, and in England and Wales, an…Read more
  •  42
    Nonideal Theorizing in Education
    Educational Theory 65 (2): 215-231. 2015.
    In this essay, Harry Brighouse responds to the collection of articles in the current issue of Educational Theory, all concerned with nonideal theorizing in education. First, he argues that some form of ideal theory is indispensable for the nonideal theorizer. Brighouse then proceeds to defend Rawls against some critics of his kind of ideal theorizing by arguing that a central feature that is often misconstrued as unduly idealizing — the full compliance assumption — in fact constrains utopianism.…Read more
  •  17
    On Alex Callinicos's Equality (review)
    with Erik Olin Wright
    Historical Materialism 10 (1): 193-222. 2002.
  •  61
    Justice
    Polity. 2005.
    The book also includes extensive discussions of the nature and purpose of political theorizing, and it asks whether theories of justice should take only social ...
  •  54
    The Political Philosophy of Cosmopolitanism (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2005.
    In a period of rapid internationalization of trade and increased labor mobility, is it relevant for nations to think about their moral obligations to others? Do national boundaries have fundamental moral significance, or do we have moral obligations to foreigners that are equal to our obligations to our compatriots? The latter position is known as cosmopolitanism, and this volume brings together a number of distinguished political philosophers and theorists to explore cosmopolitanism: what it co…Read more
  •  103
    Educational justice and socio-economic segregation in schools
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 41 (4). 2007.
    Sociologists exploring educational injustice often focus on socio-economic segregation as a central measure of injustice. The comprehensive ideal, furthermore, has the idea of socio-economic integration built into it. The current paper argues that socio-economic segregation is valuable only insofar as it serves other, more fundamental values. This matters because sometimes policy-makers will find themselves facing trade-offs between increasing integration and promoting the other, more fundamenta…Read more
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 10 (1): 127-133. 1994.
  • In my contribution today I want to talk about the place of private schooling in a society devoted to educational justice. I should say at the outset that although there are no principled reasons for opposing private schooling - certainly none in favour of the idea that the state should have a monopoly on provision - I do not share the enthusiasm that many of today's speakers have shown for private schools. Whether or not they are consistent with a just distribution of schooling is a highly conti…Read more
  •  11
    Most of the estimated 855 million people in the world (one sixth of the population) without access to schooling are women and girls. Two thirds of the 110 million school age children not in school are girls (UNGEI, 2002). This injustice has been a focus of attempts at coordinated international policy interventions since the 1990s, sometimes loosely referred to as the Education for All (EFA) movement. The first of the millennium development targets - gender equity in education - is supposed to be…Read more
  •  16
    In Defence of Educational Equality
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 29 (3): 415-420. 1995.
    The principle of educational equality is important for the plausibility of egalitarianism. I argue against John Wilson’s recent attempts to show that two particular versions of the principle are incoherent, and I rebut his argument that even if it were coherent it would be wrong to endorse it. Two other objections to this version of the principle are considered and shown not to be decisive. The principle governing the distribution of educational resources that Wilson advocates is also rejected.
  •  28
    Critical Moral Liberalism: Theory and Practice
    with Jeffrey Reiman
    Philosophical Review 108 (3): 442. 1999.
    While it forms the framework for most analytical political philosophy, liberalism is widely attacked and even ridiculed outside that small world. It is, according to one widely accepted line of thinking, tainted by the color and sex of its most prominent formulators, its use in defense of the morally indefensible behavior of imperialist states and their agents, and its presumption that the rights it prescribes are applicable to all people in all places at all times.
  •  44
    Why Should States Fund Schools?
    British Journal of Educational Studies 46 (2). 1998.
    In arguing for government withdrawal from funding and regulating schooling, James Tooley claims that equality of opportunity in education implies only that all deserve an adequate minimum education. However, he concedes the 'abstract egalitarian thesis' that all should be treated with equal concern and respect. I show that this thesis indeed implies educational equality, and that Tooley's arguments against educational equality rest on a misunderstanding of the foundations of egalitarianism.