•  370
    Personal identity, concerns, and indeterminacy
    The Monist 87 (4): 489-511. 2004.
    Let the moral question of personal identity be the following: what is the nature of the entities we should focus our prudential concerns and ascriptions of responsibility around? (If indeed we should structure these things around any entities at all.) Let the semantic question of personal identity be the question of what is the nature of the entities that ‘person’ is true of. A naive (in the sense of simple and intuitive) view would have it that the two questions are so intimately connected that…Read more
  •  347
    Neo-Fregean ontology
    Philosophical Perspectives 20 (1): 95-121. 2006.
    Neo-Fregeanism in the philosophy of mathematics consists of two main parts: the logicist thesis, that mathematics (or at least branches thereof, like arithmetic) all but reduce to logic, and the platonist thesis, that there are abstract, mathematical objects. I will here focus on the ontological thesis, platonism. Neo-Fregeanism has been widely discussed in recent years. Mostly the discussion has focused on issues specific to mathematics. I will here single out for special attention the view on …Read more
  •  176
    Williams on the Normative Silence of Indeterminacy
    Analysis 73 (2): 264-271. 2013.
    In his recent Analysis article (2012), Robert Williams considers two puzzles relating to indeterminacy. On the basis of these puzzles, he defends a seemingly radical view on the normative role of indeterminacy. He speaks of indeterminacy as ‘normatively silent’. There are two ways of understanding the view that Williams defends. On one understanding, the view ends up being indistinguishable from one of the more traditional views Williams rejects, the view that phenomena of different kinds fall u…Read more
  •  274
    Fiction, indifference, and ontology
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3). 2005.
    In this paper I outline an alternative to hermeneutic fictionalism, an alternative I call indifferentism, with the same advantages as hermeneutic fictionalism with respect to ontological issues but avoiding some of the problems that face fictionalism. The difference between indifferentism and fictionalism is this. The fictionalist about ordinary utterances of a sentence S holds, with more orthodox views, that the speaker in some sense commits herself to the truth of S. It is only that for the fi…Read more
  •  594
    The Frege–Geach problem and Kalderon's moral fictionalism
    Philosophical Quarterly 59 (237): 705-712. 2009.
    Mark Eli Kalderon has argued for a fictionalist variant of non-cognitivism. On his view, what the Frege–Geach problem shows is that standard non-cognitivism proceeds uncritically from claims about use to claims about meaning; if non-cognitivism's claims were solely about use it would be on safe ground as far as the Frege–Geach problem is concerned. I argue that Kalderon's diagnosis is mistaken: the problem concerns the non-cognitivist's account of the use of moral sentences too.
  •  294
    Recent Work on Vagueness
    Analysis 71 (2): 352-363. 2011.
    Vagueness, as discussed in the philosophical literature, is the phenomenon that paradigmatically rears its head in the sorites paradox, one prominent version of which is: One grain of sand does not make a heap. For any n, if n grains of sand do not make a heap, then n + 1 grains of sand do not make a heap. So, ten billion grains of sand do not make a heap. It is common ground that the different versions of the sorites paradox arise because of vagueness in a key expression, in this case ‘heap’. O…Read more
  •  16
    Reality and thought
    In John Shand (ed.), Central Issues of Philosophy, Wiley-blackwell. 2009.
  • Paradoxes and the Foundations of Semantics and Metaphysics
    Dissertation, Massachusetts Institute of Technology. 2000.
    Numerous philosophical problems, otherwise quite different in character, are of the following form. Certain claims which seem not only obviously true, but even constitutive of the meanings of the expressions employed, can be shown to lead to absurdity when taken together. All such problems can justly be called paradoxes. The paradoxes I examine are the liar paradox, the sorites paradox, and the personal identity paradox posed by the fission problem. ;I argue that in these cases, the claims that …Read more
  •  371
    Meaning‐Constitutivity
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (6): 559-574. 2007.
    I discuss some problems faced by the meaning‐inconsistency view on the liar and sorites paradoxes which I have elsewhere defended. Most of the discussion is devoted to the question of what a defender of the meaning‐inconsistency view should say about semantic competence
  •  231
    The picture of reality as an amorphous lump
    In Theodore Sider, John Hawthorne & Dean W. Zimmerman (eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics, Blackwell. pp. 382--96. 2008.
    (1) Abstract objects. The nominalist (as the label is used today) denies that there exist abstract objects. The platonist holds that there are abstract objects. One example is numbers. The nominalist denies that there are numbers; the platonist typically affirms it.
  •  187
    Characterizing vagueness
    Philosophy Compass 2 (6). 2007.
    Philosophy Compass 2: 896-909. (Link to Philosophy Compass.).
  •  57
    Truth
    History and Philosophy of Logic 33 (1). 2012.
    History and Philosophy of Logic, Volume 33, Issue 1, Page 106-108, February 2012