• Nietzsche and the Morality Critics
    In John Richardson & Brian Leiter (eds.), Nietzsche, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  •  28
    Moral Psychology with Nietzsche
    Oxford University Press. 2019.
    Brian Leiter draws on empirical psychology to defend a set of radical ideas from Nietzsche: there is no objectively true morality, there is no free will, no one is ever morally responsible, and our conscious thoughts play almost no significant role in our actions. Nietzsche emerges as not just a great philosopher but a prescient psychologist.
  •  65
    Rorty’s Rejection of Philosophy
    Analyse & Kritik 41 (1): 23-30. 2019.
    I argue that the real puzzle about Richard Rorty’s intellectual development is not why he gave up on ‘analytic’ philosophy-he had never been much committed to that research agenda, even before it became moribund-but why, beginning with Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (PMN), he gave up on the central concerns of philosophy going back to antiquity. In addition to Rorty’s published works, I draw on biographical information about Rorty’s undergraduate and graduate education to support this asses…Read more
  •  135
    The Truth Is Terrible
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 49 (2): 151-173. 2018.
    The “terrible” existential truths about the human situation raise Schopenhauer's question: why continue living at all? Nietzsche's answer is that only viewed in terms of aesthetic values can life itself be “justified”. But how could the fact that life exemplifies aesthetic value restore our attachment to life in the face of these terrible existential truths? I suggest that there are two keys to understanding Nietzsche's answer: first, his assimilation of aesthetic pleasure to a kind of sublimate…Read more
  •  99
    The innocence of becoming: Nietzsche against guilt
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (1): 70-92. 2019.
    ABSTRACTI offer an interpretation of Nietzsche's striking idea of ‘the innocence of becoming’, and a partial defense of its import, namely, that no one is ever morally responsible or guilty for what they do and that many of the so-called reactive attitudes are misplaced. I focus primarily, though not exclusively, on the arguments as set out in Twilight of the Idols. First, there is Nietzsche's hypothesis, partly psychological and partly historical or anthropological, that the ideas of ‘free’ act…Read more
  •  23
    A teoria nietzschiana da vontade
    Cadernos Nietzsche 38 (3): 17-49. 2017.
  • Oxford Studies in Legal Philosophy, vol. 2 (edited book)
    with L. Green
    Oxford UP. 2013.
  •  24
    Nietzsche's Naturalism and Nineteenth-Century Biology
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 48 (1): 71-82. 2017.
    Christian Emden has written an informative if sometimes philosophically frustrating book about Nietzsche’s engagement with both neo-Kantian philosophers 1 and the life sciences from the 1840s onward. Emden documents the preceding with an eye to shedding light not only on Nietzsche’s naturalism, on “what does it mean to ‘translate humanity back into nature’” as Nietzsche put it in BGE, but also on what Emden calls “the problem of normativity,” variously stated as how to “obtain an understanding o…Read more
  •  3
    Nietzsche on Morality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 729-740. 2005.
  •  22
    Nietzsche's Metaethics: Against the Privilege Readings
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 277-297. 2000.
  • In Chapters I-III, I argue that Nietzsche is a critic of "morality" in the sense of any system of values that has one or both of the following features: it presupposes the truth of certain descriptive claims about human agency, in the sense that for the evaluative categories to be intelligibly applied to persons these claims must be true ; it favors the interests of the "lowest" at the expense of the "highest" men, the embodiments of human excellence. I illustrate, in particular, how this latter…Read more
  •  2
    Is there an american furisprudence?
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17 (2): 367-387. 1997.
    BRIAN LEITER; Is There An ‘American’ Jurisprudence?, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Volume 17, Issue 2, 1 July 1997, Pages 367–387, https://doi.org/10.1093/oj.
  •  45
    Reply to Five Critics of Why Tolerate Religion?
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 10 (3): 547-558. 2016.
    This is my contribution to a symposium on my book Why Tolerate Religion?, in which I respond to essays by François Boucher and Cécile Laborde, Frederick Schauer, Corey Brettschneider, and Peter Jones. I clarify and revise my view of the sense in which some religious beliefs are “insulated from reasons and evidence” in response to the criticisms of Boucher and Laborde, but take issue with other aspects of their critique. I defend most of my original argument against utilitarian and egalitarian ob…Read more
  •  298
    Moral Facts and Best Explanations
    Social Philosophy and Policy 18 (2): 79. 2001.
    Do moral properties figure in the best explanatory account of the world? According to a popular realist argument, if they do, then they earn their ontological rights, for only properties that figure in the best explanation of experience are real properties. Although this realist strategy has been widely influential—not just in metaethics, but also in philosophy of mind and philosophy of science—no one has actually made the case that moral realism requires: namely, that moral facts really will fi…Read more
  •  62
    Realism, Hard Positivism, and Conceptual Analysis
    Legal Theory 4 (4): 533-547. 1998.
    The American Legal Realists, as I read them, are tacit legal positivists: they presuppose views about the criteria of legality that have affinities with positivist accounts of law in the sense that they employ primarily pedigree tests of legal validity. Ever since Ronald Dworkin's well-known critique of H.L.A. Hart's positivism a generation ago, however, it has been hotly contested whether there is anything about positivism as a legal theory that requires that tests of legal validity be pedigree…Read more
  •  81
    Nietzsche's theory of the will
    In Ken Gemes & Simon May (eds.), Nietzsche on freedom and autonomy, Oxford University Press. pp. 119-137. 2009.
    The essay offers a philosophical reconstruction of Nietzsche's theory of the will, focusing on (1) Nietzsche's account of the phenomenology of "willing " an action, the experience we have which leads us (causally) to conceive of ourselves as exercising our will; (2) Nietzsche's arguments that the experiences picked out by the phenomenology are not causally connected to the resulting action (at least not in a way sufficient to underwrite ascriptions of moral responsibility); and (3) Nietzsche's a…Read more
  •  88
  • Introduction
    In Brian Leiter & Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford handbook of continental philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2007.
  •  3
    The Philosophical Gourmet
    The Philosophers' Magazine 9 8-8. 2000.
  •  72
    Closet dualism and mental causation
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 28 (2): 161-181. 1998.
    Serious doubts about nonreductive materialism — the orthodoxy of the past two decades in philosophy of mind — have been long overdue. Jaegwon Kim has done perhaps the most to articulate the metaphysical problems that the new breed of materialists must confront in reconciling their physicalism with their commitment to the autonomy of the mental. Although the difficulties confronting supervenience, multiple-realizability, and mental causation have been recurring themes in his work, only mental cau…Read more
  •  37
    The Demarcation Problem in Jurisprudence: A New Case for Scepticism
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 31 (4): 663-677. 2011.
    Legal philosophers have been preoccupied with specifying the differences between two systems of normative guidance that are omnipresent in all modern human societies: law and morality. Positivists propose a solution to this ‘Demarcation Problem’ according to which the legal validity of a norm cannot depend on its being morally valid, either in all or at least some possible legal systems. The proposed analysis purports to specify the essential and necessary features of law in virtue of which this…Read more
  •  136
    The case for Nietzschean moral psychology
    In Brian Leiter & Neil Sinhababu (eds.), Nietzsche and morality, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Contemporary moral psychology has been dominated by two broad traditions, one usually associated with Aristotle, the other with Kant. The broadly Aristotelian approach emphasizes the role of childhood upbringing in the development of good moral character, and the role of such character in ethical behavior. The broadly Kantian approach emphasizes the role of freely chosen conscious moral principles in ethical behavior. We review a growing body of experimental evidence that suggests that both of t…Read more
  •  20
    Review of David Hoekema, Hoekema's Review of Wilshire (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (10). 2002.