•  119
    The Death of God and the Death of Morality
    The Monist 102 (3): 386-402. 2019.
    Nietzsche famously proclaimed the “death of God,” but in so doing it was not God’s death that was really notable—Nietzsche assumes that most reflective, modern readers realize that “the belief in the Christian god has become unbelievable” —but the implications of that belief becoming unbelievable, namely, “how much must collapse now that this faith has been undermined,” in particular, “the whole of our European morality”. What is the connection between the death of God and the death of morality?…Read more
  • Nietzsche and the Morality Critics
    In John Richardson & Brian Leiter (eds.), Nietzsche, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  •  30
    Moral Psychology with Nietzsche
    Oxford University Press. 2019.
    Brian Leiter draws on empirical psychology to defend a set of radical ideas from Nietzsche: there is no objectively true morality, there is no free will, no one is ever morally responsible, and our conscious thoughts play almost no significant role in our actions. Nietzsche emerges as not just a great philosopher but a prescient psychologist.
  •  65
    Rorty’s Rejection of Philosophy
    Analyse & Kritik 41 (1): 23-30. 2019.
    I argue that the real puzzle about Richard Rorty’s intellectual development is not why he gave up on ‘analytic’ philosophy-he had never been much committed to that research agenda, even before it became moribund-but why, beginning with Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (PMN), he gave up on the central concerns of philosophy going back to antiquity. In addition to Rorty’s published works, I draw on biographical information about Rorty’s undergraduate and graduate education to support this asses…Read more
  •  137
    The Truth Is Terrible
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 49 (2): 151-173. 2018.
    The “terrible” existential truths about the human situation raise Schopenhauer's question: why continue living at all? Nietzsche's answer is that only viewed in terms of aesthetic values can life itself be “justified”. But how could the fact that life exemplifies aesthetic value restore our attachment to life in the face of these terrible existential truths? I suggest that there are two keys to understanding Nietzsche's answer: first, his assimilation of aesthetic pleasure to a kind of sublimate…Read more
  •  91
    The innocence of becoming: Nietzsche against guilt
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 62 (1): 70-92. 2019.
    ABSTRACTI offer an interpretation of Nietzsche's striking idea of ‘the innocence of becoming’, and a partial defense of its import, namely, that no one is ever morally responsible or guilty for what they do and that many of the so-called reactive attitudes are misplaced. I focus primarily, though not exclusively, on the arguments as set out in Twilight of the Idols. First, there is Nietzsche's hypothesis, partly psychological and partly historical or anthropological, that the ideas of ‘free’ act…Read more
  •  27
    A teoria nietzschiana da vontade
    Cadernos Nietzsche 38 (3): 17-49. 2017.
  • Oxford Studies in Legal Philosophy, vol. 2 (edited book)
    with L. Green
    Oxford UP. 2013.
  •  24
    Nietzsche's Naturalism and Nineteenth-Century Biology
    Journal of Nietzsche Studies 48 (1): 71-82. 2017.
    Christian Emden has written an informative if sometimes philosophically frustrating book about Nietzsche’s engagement with both neo-Kantian philosophers 1 and the life sciences from the 1840s onward. Emden documents the preceding with an eye to shedding light not only on Nietzsche’s naturalism, on “what does it mean to ‘translate humanity back into nature’” as Nietzsche put it in BGE, but also on what Emden calls “the problem of normativity,” variously stated as how to “obtain an understanding o…Read more
  •  3
    Nietzsche on Morality
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71 (3): 729-740. 2005.
  •  23
    Nietzsche's Metaethics: Against the Privilege Readings
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 277-297. 2000.
  • In Chapters I-III, I argue that Nietzsche is a critic of "morality" in the sense of any system of values that has one or both of the following features: it presupposes the truth of certain descriptive claims about human agency, in the sense that for the evaluative categories to be intelligibly applied to persons these claims must be true ; it favors the interests of the "lowest" at the expense of the "highest" men, the embodiments of human excellence. I illustrate, in particular, how this latter…Read more
  •  4
    Is there an american furisprudence?
    Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 17 (2): 367-387. 1997.
    BRIAN LEITER; Is There An ‘American’ Jurisprudence?, Oxford Journal of Legal Studies, Volume 17, Issue 2, 1 July 1997, Pages 367–387, https://doi.org/10.1093/oj.
  •  217
    The future for philosophy (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Where does philosophy, the oldest academic subject, stand at the beginning of the new millennium? This remarkable volume brings together leading figures from most major branches of the discipline to offer answers. What remains of the "linguistic turn" in twentieth-century philosophy? How should moral philosophy respond to and incorporate developments in empirical psychology? Where might Continental and Anglophone feminist theory profitably interact? How has our understanding of ancient philosoph…Read more
  •  78
    Against the two dominant strands in the secondary literature on Nietzsche's political philosophy - one attributing to Nietzsche a kind of flat-footed commitment to aristocratic forms of social ordering, the other denying that Nietzsche has any political philosophy at all-Tamsin Shaw stakes out a new and surprising position: namely, that Nietzsche was very much concerned with the familiar question of the moral or normative legitimacy of state power, but was skeptical that with the demise of relig…Read more
  •  127
    Normativity For Naturalists
    Philosophical Issues 25 (1): 64-79. 2015.
  • Llewellyn, Karl Nickerson (1893-1962)
    In Neil J. Smelser & Paul B. Baltes (eds.), International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, Elsevier. pp. 13--8999. 2001.
  •  85
    Why Marxism Still Does Not Need Normative Theory
    Analyse & Kritik 37 (1-2): 23-50. 2015.
    Marx did not have a normative theory, that is, a theory that purported to justify, discursively and systematically, his normative opinions, to show them to be rationally obligatory or objectively valid. In this regard, Marx was obviously not alone: almost everyone, including those who lead what are widely regarded as exemplary ‘moral’ lives, decide and act on the basis of normative intuitions and inclinations that fall far short of a theory. Yet self-proclaimed Marxists like G. A. Cohen and Jurg…Read more
  • Introduction
    In The future for philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 1--23. 2004.
  •  255
    Nietzsche's theory of the will
    Philosophers' Imprint 7 1-15. 2007.
    The essay offers a philosophical reconstruction of Nietzsche’s theory of the will, focusing on (1) Nietzsche’s account of the phenomenology of “willing” an action, the experience we have which leads us (causally) to conceive of ourselves as exercising our will; (2) Nietzsche’s arguments that the experiences picked out by the phenomenology are not causally connected to the resulting action (at least not in a way sufficient to underwrite ascriptions of moral responsibility); and (3) Nietzsche’s ac…Read more
  •  2
    The Philosophical Gourmet
    The Philosophers' Magazine 8 8-8. 1999.