•  117
    Fictional names
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (4). 1988.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  114
    Literature and Truthfulness
    In James Maclaurin (ed.), Rationis Defensor, . pp. 23-31. 2012.
    How should we characterise the view that we can learn about the mind from literature? Should we say that such learning consists in acquiring knowledge of truths? That option is more attractive than it is sometimes made to seem by those who oppose propositional knowledge to practical knowledge or “knowing how”. But some writers on this topic—Lamarque and Olsen—argue that, while literature may express interesting propositions, it is not their truth that matters, but their “content”. Matters to wha…Read more
  •  110
    Arts and minds
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Philosophical questions about the arts go naturally with other kinds of questions about them. Art is sometimes said to be an historical concept. But where in our cultural and biological history did art begin? If art is related to play and imagination, do we find any signs of these things in our nonhuman relatives? Sometimes the other questions look like ones the philosopher of art has to answer. Anyone who thinks that interpretation in the arts is an activity that leaves the intentions of the au…Read more
  •  102
    The Irony in Pictures
    British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (2): 149-167. 2011.
    Pictures are sometimes said to be ironic. In many cases this is an error—the error of confusing an ironic picture with a picture of an ironic situation. Nevertheless some pictures are ironic, and there are two interestingly different ways for that to be the case. A picture may be ironic in style, in which case its irony is independent of the context in which it is presented; or a picture may be ironic by virtue of its context of presentation. Having sorted this out, we can solve two problems: wh…Read more
  •  99
    Recreative Minds
    Mind 113 (450): 329-334. 2004.
  •  93
  •  91
    The long goodbye: The imaginary language of film
    British Journal of Aesthetics 33 (3): 207-219. 1993.
  •  89
    Interpretation and objectivity
    Mind 102 (407): 413-428. 1993.
  •  86
    Telling stories
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 (54): 44-49. 2011.
    As Dr Johnson said, argument is like a crossbow: it owes its force to the mechanisms of the bow, as argument owes its force to its intrinsic rational power. But testimony is like the longbow: we cannot tell what it will do unless we know the strength of the user.
  •  82
    The Forger's Art. Forgery and the Philosophy of Art
    Philosophical Quarterly 35 (141): 435. 1985.
  •  80
    Narrative and the Psychology of Character
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 67 (1): 61-71. 2009.
  •  79
    Narrative representation of causes
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 64 (3). 2006.
  •  78
    Frege on thoughts
    Mind 89 (354): 234-248. 1980.
  •  78
    Simulation-theory, theory-theory, and the evidence from autism
    In Peter Carruthers & Peter K. Smith (eds.), Theories of Theories of Mind, Cambridge University Press. pp. 242. 1996.
  •  77
    Realism of Character and the Value of Fiction
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), Aesthetics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, Cambridge University Press. pp. 161--81. 1998.
  •  76
    McTaggart at the Movies
    Philosophy 67 (261). 1992.
    I shall argue that cinematic images do not have tense: not, at least, in the sense that has been ascribed to them by film theorists. This does not abolish time in cinema, for there can be temporal relations without tense, and temporal relations between cinematic images can indicate temporal relations between events depicted. But the dispensability of tense will require us to rethink our assumptions about what is sometimes called anachrony in cinema: the reordering of story-time by narrative, of …Read more
  •  76
    Pretence, pretending, and metarepresenting
    Mind and Language 13 (1): 35-55. 1998.
    I assess the claim that metarepresentation is a key notion in understanding the nature and development of our capacity to engage in pretence. I argue that the metarepresentational programme is unhelpful in explaining how pretence operates and, in particular, how agents distinguish pretence from belief. I sketch an alternative approach to the relations between pretending and believing. This depends on a distinction between pretending and pretence, and upon the claim that pretence stands to preten…Read more
  •  70
    Some ways to understand people
    Philosophical Explorations 11 (3). 2008.
    Shaun Gallagher and Dan Hutto claim that those once bitter rivals, simulation theory and theory-theory, are now to be treated as partners in crime. It's true that the debate has become more nuanced, with detailed suggestions abroad as to how these two approaches might peaceably divide the field. And there is common ground between them, at least to the extent that they agree on what needs to be explained. But I see no fatal flaw in what they share. In particular, I reject the idea that most inter…Read more
  •  68
    Music, Art, and Metaphysics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 471-475. 1993.
  •  67
    Actual Art, Possible Art, and Art's Definition
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 68 (3): 235-241. 2010.
  •  61
    Framing Narratives
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60 17-42. 2007.
    Marianne Dashwood was well able to imagine circumstances both favourable and unfavourable to her. But for all her romantic sensibility she was not able to imagine these things from anything other than her own point of view. ‘She expected from other people the same opinions and feelings as her own, and she judged of their motives by the immediate effect of their actions on herself.’ Unlike her sister, she could not see how the ill-crafted attentions of Mrs. Jennings could derive from a good natur…Read more
  •  58
    The analysis of thoughts
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (3). 1985.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  57
    Bergman and the Film Image
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 34 (1): 323-339. 2010.
  •  56
    Frege on thoughts: A reply
    Mind 93 (370): 256-258. 1984.
  •  51
    Reply to my critics
    Philosophical Studies 89 (2-3): 355-366. 1998.
    To Carroll I say that nonrepresentational cinema is marginal in a way that nonrepresentational painting is not, and that films consisting of words only can be pictorial. Hence, my pictorial characterization of cinema is not as problematic as he suggests. To Gaut, I say that the cinematically relevant sense of imagining is not entertaining without asserting and that he underestimates the explanatory power of a simulation-based theory of imagination. He persuades me to modify some of my claims con…Read more
  •  51
    Aliens, Too
    Analysis 53 (2). 1993.
  •  48
    Standing in the Last Ditch: On the Communicative Intentions of Fiction Makers
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (4): 351-363. 2014.
    Some of us have suggested that what fiction makers do is offer us things to imagine, that this is what is distinctive of fiction and what distinguishes it from narrative-based but assertive activities such as journalism or history. Some of us hold, further, that it is the maker's intention which confers fictional status. Many, I think, feel the intuitive appeal of this idea at the same time as they sense looming problems for any proposal about fiction's nature based straightforwardly on the iden…Read more
  •  48
    The representational revolution
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2). 2004.
  •  47
    Works of Fiction and Illocutionary Acts
    Philosophy and Literature 10 (2): 304-308. 1986.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:WORKS OF FICTION AND ILLOCUTIONARY ACTS by Gregory Currie ii O peech act theory is remarkably unhelpful in explaining what ficOtion is." So says Kendall Walton.1 My purpose here is to showjust how wrong diis judgment is. Not that I want to endorse all die attempts there have been to connect fiction with the notion of a speech act. Elsewhere I have argued diat the most prominent attempt at such a theory, the one due to John Searle, fa…Read more