• Interpreting the unreliable
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Argues for a rethinking of the standard account of narrative unreliability. Works can be unreliable in many ways, and unreliable works do not, the author claims, always have unreliable narrators. Narrative theory needs to focus more on unreliable works, less on unreliable narrators. As an example of this, the author uses Ford's The Searchers.
  •  139
    Mental simulation and motor imagery
    Philosophy of Science 64 (1): 161-80. 1997.
    Motor imagery typically involves an experience as of moving a body part. Recent studies reveal close parallels between the constraints on motor imagery and those on actual motor performance. How are these parallels to be explained? We advance a simulative theory of motor imagery, modeled on the idea that we predict and explain the decisions of others by simulating their decision-making processes. By proposing that motor imagery is essentially off-line motor action, we explain the tendency of mot…Read more
  • Interpretation in art
    In Jerrold Levinson (ed.), The Oxford handbook of aesthetics, Oxford University Press. pp. 291--306. 2003.
  •  26
    Mimesis: Metaphysics, Cognition, Pragmatics (edited book)
    with Petr Kot̓átko and Martin Pokorny
    College Publications. 2012.
    The concept of mimesis has been central to philosophical aesthetics from Aristotle to Kendall Walton: in plain terms, it highlights the links between a fictional world or a representational practice on the one hand and the real world on the other. The present collection of essays includes discussions of its general viability and pertinence and of its historical origins, as well as detailed analyses of various relevant issues regarding literature, film, theatre, images and computer games. The ind…Read more
  •  35
    Milne on the context principle
    Mind 96 (384): 543-544. 1987.
  •  1
    Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science
    Philosophical Quarterly 48 (190): 127-129. 1998.
  •  249
    Impersonal imagining: A reply to Jerrold Levinson
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (170): 79-82. 1994.
  •  337
    Imagination, delusion and hallucinations
    In Max Coltheart & Martin Davies (eds.), Mind and Language, Blackwell. pp. 168-183. 2000.
    Chris Frith has argued that a loss of the sense of agency is central to schizophrenia. This suggests a connection between hallucinations and delusions on the one hand, and the misidentification of the subject’s imaginings as perceptions and beliefs on the other. In particular, understanding the mechanisms that underlie imagination may help us to explain the puzzling phenomena of thought insertion and withdrawal. Frith sometimes states his argument in terms of a loss of metarepresentational capac…Read more
  •  48
    Imagination, Delusion and Hallucinations
    Mind and Language 15 (1): 168-183. 2000.
    Chris Frith has argued that a loss of the sense of agency is central to schizophrenia. This suggests a connection between hallucinations and delusions on the one hand, and the misidentification of the subject’s imaginings as perceptions and beliefs on the other. In particular, understanding the mechanisms that underlie imagination may help us to explain the puzzling phenomena of thought insertion and withdrawal. Frith sometimes states his argument in terms of a loss of metarepresentational capac…Read more
  • Interpretation and pragmatics
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Argues for an approach to the interpretation of text‐based works within which the idea of a communicative intention is central. The communicative approach, apart from providing detailed, illuminating, and testable theories, transposes very well from conversational exchange to the interpretation of text‐based works, and promises to illuminate aesthetic aspects of our engagement with works. Examines the consequences of this approach for the issue of pluralism about interpretation.
  •  1
    Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy, and Cognitive Science
    Philosophy 71 (278): 617-622. 1995.
  •  32
    Is factuality a matter of content?
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (5): 763-763. 1999.
    Dienes & Perner argue that there is a hierarchy of forms of implicit knowledge. One level of their hierarchy involves factuality, where it may be merely implicit that the state of affairs is supposed to be a real one rather than something imagined or fictional. I argue that the factual or fictional status of a thought or utterance cannot be a matter of concept, implicit or explicit.
  •  26
    Imagination, Delusion and Hallucinations
    Mind and Language 15 (1): 168-183. 2000.
    Chris Frith has argued that a loss of the sense of agency is central to schizophrenia. This suggests a connection between hallucinations and delusions on the one hand, and the misidentification of the subject’s imaginings as perceptions and beliefs on the other. In particular, understanding the mechanisms that underlie imagination may help us to explain the puzzling phenomena of thought insertion and withdrawal. Frith sometimes states his argument in terms of a loss of metarepresentational capac…Read more
  • Genre
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Outlines a theory of genres: of what they are, what they do, and what they explain. The central notion is that of a genre‐for‐a‐community, which depends on psychological facts concerning tendencies of expectation in the audience. The minimal conditions for a genre to be instantiated are weak; Outlines some stronger conditions which allow us to focus on self‐conscious genre‐based effects. Suggests that genre, even thus strengthened, has only a very weak explanatory role. Gives accounts of genre i…Read more
  •  212
    Imagination as motivation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (3): 201-16. 2002.
    What kinds of psychological states motivate us? Beliefs and desires are the obvious candidates. But some aspects of our behaviour suggest another idea. I have in mind the view that imagination can sometimes constitute motivation
  •  168
    Fictional truth
    Philosophical Studies 50 (2). 1986.
  •  4
    Imagination and make-believe
    In Berys Nigel Gaut & Dominic Lopes (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Aesthetics, Routledge. 2000.
  •  61
    Framing Narratives
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 60 17-42. 2007.
    Marianne Dashwood was well able to imagine circumstances both favourable and unfavourable to her. But for all her romantic sensibility she was not able to imagine these things from anything other than her own point of view. ‘She expected from other people the same opinions and feelings as her own, and she judged of their motives by the immediate effect of their actions on herself.’ Unlike her sister, she could not see how the ill-crafted attentions of Mrs. Jennings could derive from a good natur…Read more
  •  1
    Genre
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
  •  331
    Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science
    Cambridge University Press. 1995.
    This is a book about the nature of film: about the nature of moving images, about the viewer's relation to film, and about the kinds of narrative that film is capable of presenting. It represents a very decisive break with the semiotic and psychoanalytic theories of film which have dominated discussion. The central thesis is that film is essentially a pictorial medium and that the movement of film images is real rather than illusory. A general theory of pictorial representation is presented, whi…Read more
  •  117
    Fictional names
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 66 (4). 1988.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  • Introduction
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
  •  11
    Film, reality, and illusion
    In David Bordwell Noel Carroll (ed.), Post-Theory: Reconstructing Film Studies, University of Wisconsin Press. pp. 325--44. 1996.
  •  24
    Dennis Dutton , "The Forger's Art: Forgery and The Philosophy of Art" (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 35 (41): 435. 1985.
  • Documentary
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Defends the idea that documentary is a distinctive and important cinematic category, though an essentially vague one. This notion depends on that of a trace. A documentary must involve traces of its subject, and not merely testimony of it. Defines an ideal documentary as one where there is a certain kind of coherence between the narrative and the trace‐content of the work. Argues that the notion of an ideal documentary explains much in our attitude towards, and practice concerning those things w…Read more
  • Cognitive film theory
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Cognitive film theory is reckoned a powerful and distinctive, if minority position in film studies. What does it say? Argues that Bordwell's constructivism about meaning and his account of perception are not essential components of the project, which is better characterized by commitment to theses calls rationalism and realism, and by a presumption in favour of folk psychology. Cognitivists — who might be better called rationalists — should not be too cognitive, especially in matters of percepti…Read more
  • Can there be a literary philosophy of time?
    In Arts and minds, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    Many theorists have been attracted to the idea that literature can help us penetrate the mystery of time. Argues that the track record of the works they appeal to is poor. Finds some common ground with the literary philosophers, and suggests ways in which fiction might tell us things about time; But alsosuggests that there is very little to be hoped for from this programme. A belief to the contrary is largely the result of a misunderstanding about what counts as a question about time.
  •  19
    Empathy for Objects1
    In Amy Coplan & Peter Goldie (eds.), Empathy: Philosophical and Psychological Perspectives, Oxford University Press. pp. 82. 2011.