•  329
    Visible traces: Documentary and the contents of photographs
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (3): 285-297. 1999.
  • Visual conceptual art
    In Peter Goldie & Elisabeth Schellekens (eds.), Philosophy and conceptual art, Oxford University Press. pp. 33. 2007.
  •  233
    Unreliability refigured: Narrative in literature and film
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1): 19-29. 1995.
    Aims to improve an understanding of the theoretical issues in response to the influence of fiction. Four things in narrative unreliability; Relation between narration in literary fictions and film; Comprehension of narrative essentially a matter of intentional inference; Fictions misdescribed; Asymmetry between literature and film; Ambiguity and unreliability; Implied author and narrator.
  •  16
    Text without Context: Some Errors of Stanley Fish
    Philosophy and Literature 15 (2): 212-228. 1991.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Gregory Currie TEXT WITHOUT CONTEXT: SOME ERRORS OF STANLEY FISH "Intuition told him that the vast ineptitude of the venture would serve as proof that no fraud was afoot." —Jorge Luis Borges, "Tom Castro, the Implausible Imposter," in A Universal History ofInfamy There are those of us who seek unity, universality, patterns of invariance in any diverse multitude of particulars. With the interpretation of texts, the diversity is eviden…Read more
  •  211
    Work and text
    Mind 100 (3): 325-340. 1991.
  •  86
    Telling stories
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 (54): 44-49. 2011.
    As Dr Johnson said, argument is like a crossbow: it owes its force to the mechanisms of the bow, as argument owes its force to its intrinsic rational power. But testimony is like the longbow: we cannot tell what it will do unless we know the strength of the user.
  •  15
    Telling stories
    The Philosophers' Magazine 54 44-49. 2011.
    As Dr Johnson said, argument is like a crossbow: it owes its force to the mechanisms of the bow, as argument owes its force to its intrinsic rational power. But testimony is like the longbow: we cannot tell what it will do unless we know the strength of the user.
  •  133
    Visual imagery as the simulation of vision
    Mind and Language 10 (1-2): 25-44. 1995.
    Simulation Theory says we need not rely exclusively on prepositional knowledge of other minds in order to explain the actions of others. Seeking to know what you will do, I imagine myself in your situation, and see what decision I come up with. I argue that this conception of simulation naturally generalizes: various bits of our mental machine can be run‘off‐line’, fulfilling functions other than those they were made for. In particular, I suggest that visual imagery results when the visual syste…Read more
  •  48
    The representational revolution
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 62 (2). 2004.
  •  413
    The Nature of Fiction
    Cambridge University Press. 1990.
    This important book provides a theory about the nature of fiction, and about the relation between the author, the reader and the fictional text. The approach is philosophical: that is to say, the author offers an account of key concepts such as fictional truth, fictional characters, and fiction itself. The book argues that the concept of fiction can be explained partly in terms of communicative intentions, partly in terms of a condition which excludes relations of counterfactual dependence betwe…Read more
  •  8
    The film theory that never was: A nervous manifesto
    In Richard Allen & Murray Smith (eds.), Film Theory and Philosophy, Oxford University Press. pp. 42--59. 1997.
    This chapter is a manifesto of the film theory of Gregory Currie. He thinks that his work brings a connection between film and cognitive psychology. The chapter begins with a glimpse of an ideal theoretical structure and his opinion on the philosophical background against the manifesto itself. Then the theses and the arguments on film theory and the philosophy of film, moving pictures, convention, intention, and genre, and the viewer is laid out. The description includes an outline of what he th…Read more
  •  80
    The Forger's Art. Forgery and the Philosophy of Art
    Philosophical Quarterly 35 (141): 435. 1985.
  • The ontology of conceptual art
    In Peter Goldie & Elisabeth Schellekens (eds.), Philosophy and conceptual art, Oxford University Press. 2007.
  •  1
    The capacities that enable us to produce and consume art
    In Matthew Kieran & Dominic Lopes (eds.), Imagination, Philosophy, and the Arts, Routledge. pp. 293--304. 2003.
  •  474
    The moral psychology of fiction
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (2). 1995.
    What can we learn from fiction? I argue that we can learn about the consequences of a certain course of action by projecting ourselves, in imagination, into the situation of the fiction's characters
  •  102
    The Irony in Pictures
    British Journal of Aesthetics 51 (2): 149-167. 2011.
    Pictures are sometimes said to be ironic. In many cases this is an error—the error of confusing an ironic picture with a picture of an ironic situation. Nevertheless some pictures are ironic, and there are two interestingly different ways for that to be the case. A picture may be ironic in style, in which case its irony is independent of the context in which it is presented; or a picture may be ironic by virtue of its context of presentation. Having sorted this out, we can solve two problems: wh…Read more
  •  14
    The Nature of Fiction
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 50 (1): 67-68. 1992.
  •  8
    The Master of the Masek Beds: Handaxes, Art, and the Minds of Early Humans1
    In Elisabeth Schellekens & Peter Goldie (eds.), The Aesthetic Mind: Philosophy and Psychology, Oxford University Press. pp. 9. 2011.
  •  6
    Sul godimento della tragedia
    Rivista di Estetica 53 7-24. 2013.
    In this paper I consider some of the problems in moral psychology that tragic fiction brings to our attention. I consider Hume’s account of the attractions of tragedy and suggest that it is unsatisfactory. I then focus on the nature of our desires when responding to tragic representations, and argue that we need a distinction between real desires and what people have called “i-desires”. I show how we can draw this distinction in a principled way.
  •  24
    The Authentic and the Aesthetic
    American Philosophical Quarterly 22 (2). 1985.
  •  58
    The analysis of thoughts
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 (3). 1985.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  1
    Recreative Minds: Imagination in Philosophy and Psychology
    with Ian Ravenscroft
    Philosophy 79 (308): 331-335. 2004.
  •  133
    Tragedy
    Analysis 70 (4): 632-638. 2010.
  •  476
    Recreative Minds develops a philosophical theory of imagination that draws upon the latest work in psychology. This theory illuminates the use of imagination in coming to terms with art, its role in enabling us to live as social beings, and the psychological consequences of disordered imagination. The authors offer a lucid exploration of a fascinating subject.
  •  6
    To do aestheticsI
    In Matthew C. Haug (ed.), Philosophical Methodology: The Armchair or the Laboratory?, Routledge. pp. 435. 2013.
  •  48
    Standing in the Last Ditch: On the Communicative Intentions of Fiction Makers
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 72 (4): 351-363. 2014.
    Some of us have suggested that what fiction makers do is offer us things to imagine, that this is what is distinctive of fiction and what distinguishes it from narrative-based but assertive activities such as journalism or history. Some of us hold, further, that it is the maker's intention which confers fictional status. Many, I think, feel the intuitive appeal of this idea at the same time as they sense looming problems for any proposal about fiction's nature based straightforwardly on the iden…Read more
  •  70
    Some ways to understand people
    Philosophical Explorations 11 (3). 2008.
    Shaun Gallagher and Dan Hutto claim that those once bitter rivals, simulation theory and theory-theory, are now to be treated as partners in crime. It's true that the debate has become more nuanced, with detailed suggestions abroad as to how these two approaches might peaceably divide the field. And there is common ground between them, at least to the extent that they agree on what needs to be explained. But I see no fatal flaw in what they share. In particular, I reject the idea that most inter…Read more
  •  50
    Reply to my critics
    Philosophical Studies 89 (2-3): 355-366. 1998.
    To Carroll I say that nonrepresentational cinema is marginal in a way that nonrepresentational painting is not, and that films consisting of words only can be pictorial. Hence, my pictorial characterization of cinema is not as problematic as he suggests. To Gaut, I say that the cinematically relevant sense of imagining is not entertaining without asserting and that he underestimates the explanatory power of a simulation-based theory of imagination. He persuades me to modify some of my claims con…Read more
  •  114
    Literature and Truthfulness
    In James Maclaurin (ed.), Rationis Defensor, . pp. 23-31. 2012.
    How should we characterise the view that we can learn about the mind from literature? Should we say that such learning consists in acquiring knowledge of truths? That option is more attractive than it is sometimes made to seem by those who oppose propositional knowledge to practical knowledge or “knowing how”. But some writers on this topic—Lamarque and Olsen—argue that, while literature may express interesting propositions, it is not their truth that matters, but their “content”. Matters to wha…Read more