•  65
    Tractatus 6.2–6.22
    Philosophical Investigations 13 (2): 126-136. 1990.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein’s remarks 6.2-6.22 Tractatus fare well when one focuses on non-quantificational arithmetic, but they are problematic when one moves to quantificational arithmetic.
  • References
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 285-287. 2006.
  •  163
    Tarski and Proper Classes
    Analysis 40 (4): 6-11. 1980.
    In this paper the authors argue that if Tarski’s definition of truth for the calculus of classes is correct, then set theories which assert the existence of proper classes (classes which are not the member of anything) are incorrect.
  •  98
    Relativism and ontology
    Philosophical Quarterly 37 (148): 278-290. 1987.
    This paper deals with the question of whether there is objectivist truth about set-theoretic matters. The dogmatist and skeptic agree that there is such truth. They disagree about whether this truth is knowable. In contrast, the relativist says there is no objective truth to be known. Two versions of relativism are distinguished in the paper. One of these versions is defended.
  •  72
    Two concepts of truth
    Philosophical Studies 70 (1). 1993.
    In this paper the authors recapitulate, justify, and defend against criticism the extension of the redundancy theory of truth to cover a wide range of uses of ‘true’ and ‘false’. In this they are guided by the work of A. N. Prior. They argue Prior was right about the scope and limits of the redundancy theory and that the line he drew between those uses of ‘true’ which are and are not susceptible to treatment via redundancy serves to distinguish two important and mutually irreducible types of tru…Read more
  •  4
    Quine' way out
    Analysis 36 (1): 28-37. 1975.
  •  149
    Quantifying over the reals
    Synthese 101 (1). 1994.
    Peter Geach proposed a substitutional construal of quantification over thirty years ago. It is not standardly substitutional since it is not tied to those substitution instances currently available to us; rather, it is pegged to possible substitution instances. We argue that (i) quantification over the real numbers can be construed substitutionally following Geach's idea; (ii) a price to be paid, if it is that, is intuitionism; (iii) quantification, thus conceived, does not in itself relieve us …Read more
  • Quine's way out
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 36 (1): 28. 1975.
  •  4
    Prior on propositional identity
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 36 (4): 182. 1976.
  •  106
    Quine’s Way Out
    Analysis 36 (1): 28-37. 1975.
    As a way of dealing with the semantical paradoxes Quine has suggested: that semantical expressions such as ‘true’ and ‘true of’ be used with numerical subscripts; that when a truth locution T is applied to a sentence S, the subscript on T is greater than any within S; otherwise, the result of applying T to S is ill formed. A problem is that this introduces infinitely many semantical primitives. The paper suggests a way around the problem. The paper raises a further problem, leaving it open whet…Read more
  •  4
    Prior's Theory of Propositions
    Analysis 37 (3): 104-112. 1977.
  •  129
    Prior’s Theory of Propositions
    Analysis 37 (3): 104-112. 1977.
    Prior propounded a theory that, if correct, explains how it is possible for a statement about propositions to be true even if there are no propositions. The major feature of his theory is his treatment of sentence letters as bindable variables in non-referential positions. His theory, however, does not include a semantical account of the resulting quantification. The paper tries to fill that gap.
  •  10
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 151-173. 1991.
  •  61
    Prior on Propositional Identity
    Analysis 36 (4): 182-184. 1976.
    Let A, B, C stand for sentences expressing propositions; let A be a component of C; let C A/B be just like C except for replacing some occurrence of A in C by an occurrence of B; let = be a binary connective for propositional identity read as ‘the proposition that __ is the very same proposition as …’. Then authors defend adding ‘from C = C A/B infer A = B’ to Prior’s rules for propositional identity, appearing in OBJECTS OF THOUGHT.
  • Paradox and semantical correctness
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 39 (4): 166. 1979.
  •  76
    Paradox and Semantical Correctness
    Analysis 39 (4): 166-169. 1979.
    In a series of papers R. L. Martin propounds a theory for dealing with the semantical paradoxes. This paper is a criticism of that theory.
  •  732
    Null Sentences
    Iyyun, The Jewish Philosophical Quarterly 48 23-36. 1999.
    In Tractatus, Wittgenstein held that there are null sentences – prominently including logical truths and the truths of mathematics. He says that such sentences are without sense (sinnlos), that they say nothing; he also denies that they are nonsensical (unsinning). Surely it is what a sentence says which is true or false. So if a sentence says nothing, how can it be true or false? The paper discusses the issue.
  •  4
    More on propositional identity
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
  • Preface
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 90 27-29. 2006.
  •  284
    Offices and God
    Sophia 29 (3): 29-34. 1990.
    Pavel Tichy presents an interpretation of Anselm’s Proslogion III argument. Tichy presents an interpretation of this argument and raises doubts about one of the premises. The authors contend that Tichy’s interpretation of Anselm is wrong. The argument Tichy comes to raise doubts about is not Anselm’s.
  •  40
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophishe Studien 41 150-173. 1991.
    A case against Prior’s theory of propositions goes thus: (1) everyday propositional generalizations are not substitutional; (2) Priorean quantifications are not objectual; (3) quantifications are substitutional if not objectual; (4) thus, Priorean quantifications are substitutional; (5) thus that Priorean quantifications are not ontologically committed to propositions provides no basis for a similar claim about our everyday propositional generalizations. Prior agrees with (1) and (2). He rejects…Read more
  •  48
    Offices and God
    with Charles Saywood
    Sophia 29 (3): 29-34. 1990.
  •  12
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 151-173. 1991.
  •  120
    Moral relativism and deontic logic
    Synthese 85 (1). 1990.
    If a native of India asserts "Killing cattle is wrong" and a Nebraskan asserts "Killing cattle is not wrong", and both judgments agree with their respective moralities and both moralities are internally consistent, then the moral relativist says both judgments are fully correct. At this point relativism bifurcates. One branch which we call content relativism denies that the two people are contradicting each other. The idea is that the content of a moral judgment is a function of the overall mora…Read more
  •  18
    Expressions and tokens
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 41 (4): 181. 1981.
  •  7
    Is moral relativism consistent?
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 45 (1): 40. 1985.
  •  56
    More on propositional identity
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
    We give a semantical account of propositional identity which is stronger than mutual entailment. That is, according to our account: (1) if A = B is true in a model, so are A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A. (2) There exist models m such that A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A are true in m but A = B is not true in m. According to our account the following rule is sound: (3) from (.. A..) = (.. B..) infer A = B. The paper is a response to a paper by James Freeman to an earlier paper by us.
  •  318
    Is Moral Relativism Consistent?
    Analysis 45 (1): 40-44. 1985.
    Let C1 and C2 be distinct moral codes formulated in English. Let C1 contain a norm N and C2 its negation. The paper construes the moral relativist as saying that if both codes are consistent, then, in the strongest sense of correctness applicable to moral norms, they are also both correct in the sense that they contain only correct moral norms. If we believe that the physical statements of English are true (false) in English, we will reject an analogous statement made of physical theories. We wi…Read more
  •  53
    Is English inconsistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3). 1980.
    The significance of the semantical paradoxes for natural languages is examined. If Tarski’s reflections on the issue are correct, English is inconsistent. Paul Ziff responds to Tarskian reflections by arguing to the conclusion that no natural language is or can be inconsistent. The authors reject Ziff’s argument, but they defend something similar to its conclusion: no language, natural or otherwise, is or can be inconsistent in the way that Tarski holds languages capable of formulating the Epime…Read more