•  65
    Two concepts of truth
    Philosophical Studies 70 (1). 1993.
    In this paper the authors recapitulate, justify, and defend against criticism the extension of the redundancy theory of truth to cover a wide range of uses of ‘true’ and ‘false’. In this they are guided by the work of A. N. Prior. They argue Prior was right about the scope and limits of the redundancy theory and that the line he drew between those uses of ‘true’ which are and are not susceptible to treatment via redundancy serves to distinguish two important and mutually irreducible types of tru…Read more
  •  65
    Tractatus 6.2–6.22
    Philosophical Investigations 13 (2): 126-136. 1990.
    It is argued that Wittgenstein’s remarks 6.2-6.22 Tractatus fare well when one focuses on non-quantificational arithmetic, but they are problematic when one moves to quantificational arithmetic.
  •  64
    More on Propositional Identity
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
    We give a semantical account of propositional identity which is stronger than mutual entailment. That is, according to our account: (1) if A = B is true in a model, so are A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A. (2) There exist models m such that A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A are true in m but A = B is not true in m. According to our account the following rule is sound: (3) from (.. A..) = (.. B..) infer A = B. The paper respondes to a criticism of an earlier paper by James Freeman
  •  61
    Prior on Propositional Identity
    Analysis 36 (4): 182-184. 1976.
    Let A, B, C stand for sentences expressing propositions; let A be a component of C; let C A/B be just like C except for replacing some occurrence of A in C by an occurrence of B; let = be a binary connective for propositional identity read as ‘the proposition that __ is the very same proposition as …’. Then authors defend adding ‘from C = C A/B infer A = B’ to Prior’s rules for propositional identity, appearing in OBJECTS OF THOUGHT.
  •  58
    This book says Prior claims: (1) that a sentence never names; (2) what a sentence says cannot be otherwise signified; and (3) that a sentence says what it says whatever the type of its occurrence; (4) and that quantifications binding sentential variables are neither eliminable, substitutional, nor referential. The book develops and defends (1)-(3). It also defends (4) against the sorts of strictures on quantification of such philosophers as Quine and Davidson.
  •  56
    More on propositional identity
    Analysis 39 (3): 129-132. 1979.
    We give a semantical account of propositional identity which is stronger than mutual entailment. That is, according to our account: (1) if A = B is true in a model, so are A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A. (2) There exist models m such that A 'validates' B and B 'validates' A are true in m but A = B is not true in m. According to our account the following rule is sound: (3) from (.. A..) = (.. B..) infer A = B. The paper is a response to a paper by James Freeman to an earlier paper by us.
  •  54
    What is an infinite expression?
    Philosophia 16 (1): 45-60. 1986.
    The following syllogism is considered: a string is not an expression unless it is tokenable; no one can utter, write, or in anyway token an infinite string; so no infinite string is an expression. The second premise is rejected. But the tokenability of an infinite sentence is not sufficient for it being an infinite expression. A further condition is that no finite sentence expresses that sentence’s truth-conditions. So it is an open question whether English contains infinite expressions.
  •  52
    Theories of truth and semantical primitives
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 6 (1). 1977.
    Robert cummins has recently attacked this line of argument: if p is a semantically primitive predicate of a first order language l, then p requires its own clause in the definition of satisfaction integral to a definition of truth of l. thus if l has infinitely many such p, the satisfaction clause cannot be completed and truth for l will remain undefined. against this cummins argues that a single clause in a general base theory for l can specify satisfaction conditions for even infinitely many s…Read more
  •  51
    Is English inconsistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3). 1980.
    The significance of the semantical paradoxes for natural languages is examined. If Tarski’s reflections on the issue are correct, English is inconsistent. Paul Ziff responds to Tarskian reflections by arguing to the conclusion that no natural language is or can be inconsistent. The authors reject Ziff’s argument, but they defend something similar to its conclusion: no language, natural or otherwise, is or can be inconsistent in the way that Tarski holds languages capable of formulating the Epime…Read more
  •  49
    In this book a non-realist philosophy of mathematics is presented. Two ideas are essential to its conception. These ideas are (i) that pure mathematics--taken in isolation from the use of mathematical signs in empirical judgement--is an activity for which a formalist account is roughly correct, and (ii) that mathematical signs nonetheless have a sense, but only in and through belonging to a system of signs with empirical application. This conception is argued by the two authors and is critically…Read more
  •  48
    Can a language have indenumerably many expressions?
    History and Philosophy of Logic 4 (1-2): 73-82. 1983.
    A common assumption among philosophers is that every language has at most denumerably many expressions. This assumption plays a prominent role in many philosophical arguments. Recently formal systems with indenumerably many elements have been developed. These systems are similar to the more familiar denumerable first-order languages. This similarity makes it appear that the assumption is false. We argue that the assumption is true
  •  48
    Offices and God
    with Charles Saywood
    Sophia 29 (3): 29-34. 1990.
  •  48
    Ineffability in Frege's logic
    Philosophical Studies 24 (4). 1973.
  •  46
    Redundant truth
    Ratio 5 (1): 24-37. 1992.
    A strong and weak version of the redundancy theory of truth are distinguished. An argument put forth by Michael Dummett concludes that the weak version is vitiated by truth-value gaps. The weak version is defended against this argument. The strong version, however, is vitiated by truth-value gaps.
  •  39
    Various authors of logic texts are cited who either suggest or explicitly state that the Gödel incompleteness result shows that some unprovable sentence of arithmetic is true. Against this, the paper argues that the matter is one of philosophical controversy, that it is not a mathematical or logical issue.
  •  39
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophishe Studien 41 150-173. 1991.
    A case against Prior’s theory of propositions goes thus: (1) everyday propositional generalizations are not substitutional; (2) Priorean quantifications are not objectual; (3) quantifications are substitutional if not objectual; (4) thus, Priorean quantifications are substitutional; (5) thus that Priorean quantifications are not ontologically committed to propositions provides no basis for a similar claim about our everyday propositional generalizations. Prior agrees with (1) and (2). He rejects…Read more
  •  33
    A fregean principle
    History and Philosophy of Logic 19 (3): 125-135. 1998.
    Frege held that the result of applying a predicate to names lacks reference if any of the names lack reference. We defend the principle against a number of plausible objections. We put forth an account of consequence for a first-order language with identity in which the principle holds
  •  32
  •  31
    A semantical account of the vicious circle principle
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 20 (3): 595-598. 1979.
    Here we give a semantical account of propositional quantification that is intended to formally represent Russell’s view that one cannot express a proposition about "all" propositions. According to the account the authors give, Russell’s view bears an interesting relation to the view that there are no sets which are members of themselves.
  •  29
    Anderson and Belnap devise a model theory for entailment on which propositional identity equals proposional coentailment. This feature can be reasonably questioned. The authors devise two extensions of Anderson and Belnap’s model theory. Both systems preserve Anderson and Belnap’s results for entailment, but distinguish coentailment from identity.
  •  28
    Do we need models?
    Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 28 (3): 414-422. 1987.
    The aim of this paper is to provide a nondenotational semantics for first-order languages which will match one for one each distribution of truth-values available in terms of a denotational semantics.
  •  24
    Crowell on Nietzsche on Truth
    International Studies in Philosophy 19 (2): 19-28. 1987.
  •  18
    Expressions and tokens
    with Alonso Church
    Analysis 41 (4): 181. 1981.
  •  13
    The Internal/External Question
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 47 (1): 31-41. 1994.
  •  11
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 151-173. 1991.
  •  10
    Prior and Lorenzen on Quantification
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 41 (1): 151-173. 1991.
  •  10
    The Internal/External Question
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 47 (1): 31-41. 1994.
  •  7
    Is English Consistent?
    Erkenntnis 15 (3): 343. 1980.
  •  6
    Quine's Way Out
    with Charles Sayward
    Analysis 36 (1): 28. 1975.