•  157
    McDowell, Davidson, and SpontaneityMind and World
    with Richard Rorty
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2): 389. 1998.
  •  826
    What myth?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (4). 2007.
    In previous work I urged that the perceptual experience we rational animals enjoy is informed by capacities that belong to our rationality, and - in passing - that something similar holds for our intentional action. In his Presidential Address, Hubert Dreyfus argued that I thereby embraced a myth, "the Myth of the Mental". According to Dreyfus, I cannot accommodate the phenomenology of unreflective bodily coping, and its importance as a background for the conceptual capacities exercised in refle…Read more
  •  1469
  •  582
    Wittgensteinian “quietism”
    Common Knowledge 15 (3): 365-372. 2009.
    In his Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein describes, and represents himself as pursuing, a way of doing philosophy without putting forward philosophical theses. I exemplify his approach with a sketch of his treatment of rule following. I focus in particular on the simple case of following a signpost, conceived as an expression of a rule for getting to a destination. Wittgenstein uncovers a threat that we will find it mysterious how one could learn from a signpost which way to go, and he d…Read more
  •  197
    Wittgenstein and the Inner World
    Journal of Philosophy 86 (11): 643-644. 1989.
  •  764
    The content of perceptual experience
    Philosopical Quarterly 44 (175): 190-205. 1994.
  •  1016
    Tyler Burge on disjunctivism
    Philosophical Explorations 13 (3): 243-255. 2010.
    In Burge 2005, Tyler Burge reads disjunctivism as the denial that there are explanatorily relevant states in common between veridical perceptions and corresponding illusions. He rejects the position as plainly inconsistent with what is known about perception. I describe a disjunctive approach to perceptual experience that is immune to Burge's attack. The main positive moral concerns how to think about fallibility.
  •  151
    Tyler Burge on disjunctivism
    Philosophical Explorations 16 (3): 259-279. 2010.
    In McDowell, I responded to Burge's attack on disjunctivism. In Burge Burge rejects my response. He stands by his main claim that disjunctivism is incompatible with the science of perception, and in a supplementary spirit he argues against the detail of my attempt to defend disjunctivism. Here I explain how disjunctivism is compatible with the science, and I respond to some of Burge's supplementary arguments.
  •  194
    Response to Stephen Houlgate
    The Owl of Minerva 41 (1/2): 27-38. 2009.
    I argue that Stephen Houlgate misstates an element in the Kantian background to my reading of “Lordship and Bondage” (§2). He misreads my remarks about the need to see Hegel’s moves there in the context of the progression towards absolute knowing (§3), and, partly consequently, he fails to engage with the motivation for my reading (§4). And he does not understand the way my reading exploits the concept of allegory (§5).
  •  105
    Response to Stephen Houlgate
    The Owl of Minerva 41 (1-2): 27-38. 2009.
    I argue that Stephen Houlgate misstates an element in the Kantian background to my reading of “Lordship and Bondage” (§2). He misreads my remarks about the need to see Hegel’s moves there in the context of the progression towards absolute knowing (§3), and, partly consequently, he fails to engage with the motivation for my reading (§4). And he does not understand the way my reading exploits the concept of allegory (§5).
  •  322
    Reply to Gibson, Byrne, and Brandom
    Philosophical Issues 7 283-300. 1996.
  •  92
    Reply to Kathrin Glüer
    Theoria 70 (2-3): 213-215. 2004.
  •  439
    Response to Dreyfus
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 50 (4). 2007.
    In previous work I urged that the perceptual experience we rational animals enjoy is informed by capacities that belong to our rationality, and - in passing - that something similar holds for our intentional action. In his Presidential Address, Hubert Dreyfus argued that I thereby embraced a myth, "the Myth of the Mental". According to Dreyfus, I cannot accommodate the phenomenology of unreflective bodily coping, and its importance as a background for the conceptual capacities exercised in refle…Read more
  •  160
    Review: Reply to Commentators (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2). 1998.
  •  79
    Precis of Mind and WorldMind and World
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2): 365. 1998.
  •  45
    Precis of Mind and world
    In Enrique Villanueva (ed.), Perception, Ridgeview. pp. 231--9. 1996.
  •  266
    Précis of "mind and world" (review)
    Philosophical Issues 7 231-239. 1996.
  •  614
    Perceptual Experience: Both Relational and Contentful
    European Journal of Philosophy 21 (1): 144-157. 2013.
  •  729
  •  72
    5 Naturalism in the Philosophy of Mind
    In Mario De Caro & David Macarthur (eds.), Naturalism in Question, Harvard University Press. pp. 91-105. 2004.
  •  436
  •  305
    Mind and World
    with Huw Price
    Philosophical Books 38 (3): 169-181. 1994.
    How do rational minds make contact with the world? The empiricist tradition sees a gap between mind and world, and takes sensory experience, fallible as it is, to provide our only bridge across that gap. In its crudest form, for example, the traditional idea is that our minds consult an inner realm of sensory experience, which provides us with evidence about the nature of external reality. Notoriously, however, it turns out to be far from clear that there is any viable conception of experience w…Read more
  •  102
    Perception and Rational ConstraintMind and World
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (2): 369. 1998.
  •  1
    Criteria, defeasibility, and knowledge
    In Jonathan Dancy (ed.), Perceptual Knowledge, Oxford University Press. 1988.
  •  722
    Mind and World
    Harvard University Press. 1994.
    Much as we would like to conceive empirical thought as rationally grounded in experience, pitfalls await anyone who tries to articulate this position, and ...
  •  61
    Theaetetus (edited book)
    Clarendon Press. 1973.
    The Theaetetus is a remarkably rich dialogue that raises any number of important epistemological questions, and it rewards careful study. By systematically and thoroughly examining the text and by exploring the issues Plato raises in terms of modern epistemic concerns, Platos Theaetetus adds anew and helpful perspective to the ever growing body of scholarship on this pivotal dialogue.-Ancient Philosophy.
  • Truth and Meaning. Essays in Semantics
    with G. Evans
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 166 (4): 435-437. 1976.
  •  257
    Knowledge and the internal revisited
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (1): 97-105. 2002.
    In “Knowledge and the Social Articulation of the Space of Reasons,” Robert Brandom reads my “Knowledge and the Internal” as sketching a position that, when properly elaborated, opens into his own social-perspectival conception of knowledge . But this depends on taking me to hold that there cannot be justification for a belief sufficient to exclude the possibility that the belief is false. And that is exactly what I argued against in “Knowledge and the Internal.” Seeing that P constitutes falseho…Read more