•  9
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (4): 654-657. 1996.
  •  21
    Spacetime Visualisation and the Intelligibility of Physical Theories
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 32 (2): 243-265. 2001.
  •  44
    This paper approaches the scientific realism question from a naturalistic perspective. On the basis of a historical case study of the work of James Clerk Maxwell and Ludwig Boltzmann on the kinetic theory of gases, it shows that scientists’ views about the epistemological status of theories and models typically interact with their scientific results. Subsequently, the implications of this result for the current realism debate are analysed. The case study supports Giere’s moderately realist view …Read more
  •  1
    Proceedings of EPSA09 (edited book)
    Springer. 2012.
    This is a collection of high-quality research papers in the philosophy of science, deriving from papers presented at the second meeting of the European Philosophy of Science Association in Amsterdam, October 2009.
  •  344
    The epistemic value of understanding
    Philosophy of Science 76 (5): 585-597. 2009.
    This article analyzes the epistemic value of understanding and offers an account of the role of understanding in science. First, I discuss the objectivist view of the relation between explanation and understanding, defended by Carl Hempel and J. D. Trout. I challenge this view by arguing that pragmatic aspects of explanation are crucial for achieving the epistemic aims of science. Subsequently, I present an analysis of these pragmatic aspects in terms of ‘intelligibility’ and a contextual accoun…Read more
  •  183
    Scientific understanding: truth or dare?
    Synthese 192 (12): 3781-3797. 2015.
    It is often claimed—especially by scientific realists—that science provides understanding of the world only if its theories are (at least approximately) true descriptions of reality, in its observable as well as unobservable aspects. This paper critically examines this ‘realist thesis’ concerning understanding. A crucial problem for the realist thesis is that (as study of the history and practice of science reveals) understanding is frequently obtained via theories and models that appear to be h…Read more
  •  65
    I argue that scientific explanation has a pragmatic dimension that is epistemically relevant. Philosophers with an objectivist approach to scientific explanation (e.g. Hempel, Trout) hold that the pragmatic aspects of explanation do not have any epistemic import. I argue against this view by focusing on the role of models in scientific explanation. Applying recent accounts of modelling (Cartwright, Morgan and Morrison) to a case-study of nineteenth-century physics, I analyse the pragmatic dimens…Read more
  •  98
    Philosophy and the kinetic theory of gases
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (1): 31-62. 1996.
    This article examines the role of philosophy in the development of the kinetic theory of gases. Two opposing accounts of this role, by Peter Clark and John Nyhof, are discussed and criticized. Contrary to both accounts, it is argued that philosophical views of scientists can fundamentally influence the results of their scientific work. This claim is supported by a detailed analysis of the philosophical views of Maxwell and Boltzmann, and of their work on the kinetic theory, especially concerning…Read more
  •  46
    Review of "Quantum Dialogue - The Making of a Revolution" by Mara Beller
  •  168
    Ludwig Boltzmann's Bildtheorie and Scientific Understanding
    Synthese 119 (1-2): 113-134. 1999.
    Boltzmann’s Bildtheorie, which asserts that scientific theories are ‘mental pictures’ having at best a partial similarity to reality, was a core element of his philosophy of science. The aim of this article is to draw attention to a neglected aspect of it, namely its significance for the issue of scientific explanation and understanding, regarded by Boltzmann as central goals of science. I argue that, in addition to being an epistemological view of the interpretation of scientific theories Boltz…Read more
  • Hoe wetenschappers de wereld begrijpen
    Wijsgerig Perspectief 51 (2): 6. 2011.
    Een van de centrale doelen van wetenschap is het begrijpen van de wereld om ons heen. Wetenschappers geven beschrijvingen van verschijnselen en doen voorspellingen, maar bovenal trachten ze de verschijnselen te verklaren – en wetenschappelijke verklaringen leiden tot begrip. Of het nu het ontstaan van het universum betreft, het gedrag van levende organismen of de huidige sociale en economische ontwikkelingen, wetenschap streeft naar begrip ervan. En niet alleen wetenschappers zelf zijn geïnteres…Read more
  •  33
    EPSA Philosophy of Science: Amsterdam 2009 (edited book)
    Springer. 2011.
    Amsterdam 2009 Henk W. De Regt ... Alan C. Love 16.1 When Philosophers of Science Disagree According to John Norton there are no universal rules of inductive inference (Norton 2003). Every formal theory put forward thus far (e.g., ...
  •  154
    Introduction: Simulation, Visualization, and Scientific Understanding
    Perspectives on Science 22 (3): 311-317. 2014.
    Only a decade ago, the topic of scientific understanding remained one that philosophers of science largely avoided. Earlier discussions by Hempel and others had branded scientific understanding a mere subjective state or feeling, one to be studied by psychologists perhaps, but not an important or fruitful focus for philosophers of science. Even as scientific explanation became a central topic in philosophy of science, little attention was given to understanding. Over the last decade, however, th…Read more
  •  186
    Erwin Schrödinger, Anschaulichkeit, and quantum theory
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (4): 461-481. 1997.
    Early in 1926 Erwin Schrodinger presented his famous theory of wave mechanics to account for atomic phenomena. It is often assumed that Schrodinger’s work reflected a realist philosophy. In this article, I will argue that this assumption is incorrect.
  •  15
    Erwin Schrödinger, Anschaulichkeit, and quantum theory
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 28 (4): 461-481. 1997.
  •  35
    Explaining the splendour of science
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (1): 155-165. 1998.
  •  31
    From Explanation to Understanding: Normativity Lost?
    Journal for General Philosophy of Science / Zeitschrift für Allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 50 (3): 327-343. 2019.
    In recent years, scientific understanding has become a focus of attention in philosophy of science. Since understanding is typically associated with the pragmatic and psychological dimensions of explanation, shifting the focus from explanation to understanding may induce a shift from accounts that embody normative ideals to accounts that provide accurate descriptions of scientific practice. Not surprisingly, many ‘friends of understanding’ sympathize with a naturalistic approach to the philosoph…Read more
  •  32
    Beauty in physical science circa 2000
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 16 (1). 2002.
    This Article does not have an abstract
  •  32
    While the relation between visualization and scientific understanding has been a topic of long-standing discussion, recent developments in physics have pushed the boundaries of this debate to new and still unexplored realms. For it is claimed that, in certain theories of quantum gravity, spacetime ‘disappears’: and this suggests that one may have sensible physical theories in which spacetime is completely absent. This makes the philosophical question whether such theories are intelligible, even …Read more
  •  158
    Discussion note: Making sense of understanding
    Philosophy of Science 71 (1): 98-109. 2004.
    J.D. Trout (2002) presents a challenge to all theorists of scientific explanation who appeal to the notion of understanding. Trout denounces understanding as irrelevant, if not dangerous, from an epistemic perspective and he endorses a radically objectivist view of explanation instead. In this note I accept Trout's challenge. I criticize his argument and defend a non-objectivist, pragmatic conception of understanding that is epistemically relevant.
  •  44
    Are Physicists’Philosophies Irrelevant Idiosyncrasies?
    Philosophica 58 (2): 125-151. 1996.
  •  46
    While the relation between visualization and scientific understanding has been a topic of long-standing discussion, recent developments in physics have pushed the boundaries of this debate to new and still unexplored realms. For it is claimed that, in certain theories of quantum gravity, spacetime ‘disappears’: and this suggests that one may have sensible physical theories in which spacetime is completely absent. This makes the philosophical question whether such theories are intelligible, even …Read more
  •  403
    A Contextual Approach to Scientific Understanding
    Synthese 144 (1): 137-170. 2005.
    Achieving understanding of nature is one of the aims of science. In this paper we offer an analysis of the nature of scientific understanding that accords with actual scientific practice and accommodates the historical diversity of conceptions of understanding. Its core idea is a general criterion for the intelligibility of scientific theories that is essentially contextual: which theories conform to this criterion depends on contextual factors, and can change in the course of time. Our analysis…Read more
  •  13
    Mara Beller, Quantum Dialogue – The Making of a Revolution (review)
    Erkenntnis 56 (2): 247-252. 2002.