• Hegel. Erinnerung, Wahrnehmung, Wissen (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 56 (2). 2002.
  •  25
    Defending the One Percent?
    The Harvard Review of Philosophy 21 106-112. 2014.
    This paper discusses and criticizes Greg Mankiw's recent defense of "the one percent".
  •  22
    Coercion and the Varieties of Free Action
    Ideas Y Valores 52 (122): 31-49. 2003.
    Are we free? What does "freedom" mean here? In the following, I shall only focus with freedom of action. My main thesis is that there is not just one basic type of free action but more. Philosophers, however, tend to assume that there is just one way to act freely. Hence, a more detailed analysis of free action is being called for. I will distinguish between different kinds of free action and discuss the relations between them. The analysis of different types of coercion will lead to a different…Read more
  •  103
    The case for contexualism
    Analysis 70 (1): 149-160. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
  •  28
    Begrenzte Erkenntnisse?
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 58 (3): 483-489. 2010.
    This is a crtiical discussion of Gabriel's "An den Grenzen der Erkenntnistheorie".
  •  168
    On Reflection
    Philosophical Quarterly 64 (256): 510-512. 2014.
    Review of Kornblith, "On Reflection".
  •  56
    Knowledge, Assertion, and Inference
    Acta Analytica 29 (4): 487-490. 2014.
    This paper argues that three plausible principles are mutually inconsistent: One ought to assert only what one knows; If it is proper to assert some proposition q, then it is, barring special and not very common circumstances, proper to assert any proposition p from which q has been competently inferred; and Some propositions are both properly assertible and known by competent inference from propositions which one does not know. Each pair of two principles constitutes an argument against the rem…Read more
  •  101
    Suppose someone hears a loud noise and at the same time sees a yellow flash. It seems hard to deny that the person can experience loudness and yellowness together. However, since loudness is experienced by the auditory sense whereas yellowness is experienced by the visual sense it also seems hard to explain how.
  •  33
    Hume variations
    Philosophical Books 46 (3): 246-253. 2005.
    Review of Fodor, "Hume Variations".
  • Der Denker als Seiltänzer. Ludwig Wittgenstein über Religion, Mystik und Ethik (review)
    Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung 57 (1). 2003.
  •  22
    Reid on Ethics – Sabine Roeser (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 61 (245): 856-859. 2011.
  •  819
    Nozick's defense of closure
    In Kelly Becker & Tim Black (eds.), The Sensitivity Principle in Epistemology, Cambridge University Press. pp. 11--27. 2012.
    This paper argues against common views that at least in many cases Robert Nozick is not forced to deny common closure principles. More importantly, Nozick does not – despite first (and second) appearances and despite his own words – deny closure. On the contrary, he is defending a more sophisticated and complex principle of closure. This principle does remarkably well though it is not without problems. It is surprising how rarely Nozick’s principle of closure has been discussed. He should be see…Read more
  •  72
    I Know. Modal Epistemology and Scepticism
    Philosophical Quarterly 64 (257): 640-644. 2014.
    Review of Freitag, "I know".
  •  370
    Epistemic contrastivism is the view that knowledge is a ternary relation between a person, a proposition and a set of contrast propositions. This view is in tension with widely shared accounts of practical reasoning: be it the claim that knowledge of the premises is necessary for acceptable practical reasoning based on them or sufficient for the acceptability of the use of the premises in practical reasoning, or be it the claim that there is a looser connection between knowledge and practical re…Read more
  •  96
    Three Doors, Two Players, and Single-Case Probabilities
    American Philosophical Quarterly 42 (1). 2005.
    The well known Monty Hall-problem has a clear solution if one deals with a long enough series of individual games. However, the situation is different if one switches to probabilities in a single case. This paper presents an argument for Monty Hall situations with two players (not just one, as is usual). It leads to a quite general conclusion: One cannot apply probabilistic considerations (for or against any of the strategies) to isolated single cases. If one does that, one cannot but violate a …Read more
  •  296
    Contextualism and the Factivity Problem
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 76 (3): 580-602. 2008.
    Epistemological contextualism ‐ the claim that the truth‐value of knowledge‐attributions can vary with the context of the attributor ‐ has recently faced a whole series of objections. The most serious one, however, has not been discussed much so far: the factivity objection. In this paper, I explain what the objection is and present three different versions of the objection. I then show that there is a good way out for the contextualist. However, in order to solve the problem the contextualist h…Read more
  •  49
    On the Subtleties of Reidian Pragmatism: A Reply to Magnus
    Journal of Scottish Philosophy 2 (1): 73-77. 2004.
    In this paper I respond to P.D. Magnus’ critique of an earlier paper of mine on Thomas Reid’s theory of common sense. In the earlier paper (The Scottish Pragmatist? The Dilemma of Common Sense and the Pragmatist Way Out, Reid Studies 2, 1999, 47-57) I argued that Reid faces a dilemma between dogmatism and scepticism but that there are also hints in his work towards a pragmatist way out of the problem. P.D. Magnus, in a response to this paper (Reid’s Dilemma and the Uses of Pragmatism, Journal of…Read more
  •  152
    Knowledge and Dogmatism
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (250): 1-19. 2013.
    There is a sceptical puzzle according to which knowledge appears to license an unacceptable kind of dogmatism. Here is a version of the corresponding sceptical argument: (1) If a subject S knows a proposition p, then it is OK for S to ignore all evidence against p as misleading; (2) It is never OK for any subject to ignore any evidence against their beliefs as misleading; (3) Hence, nobody knows anything.I distinguish between different versions of the puzzle (mainly a ‘permissibility’ version an…Read more
  •  160
    Factivity and contextualism
    Analysis 70 (1): 82-89. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation).
  •  102
    Theory Choice and the Intransitivity of 'Is a Better Theory Than'
    Philosophy of Science 72 (1): 231-240. 2005.
    There is a very plausible principle of the transitivity of justifying reasons. It says that if "p" is better justified than "q" (all things considered) and "q" better than "r", then "p" is better justified than "r" (all things considered). There is a corresponding principle of rational theory choice. Call one theory "a better theory than" another theory if all criteria of theory choice considered (explanatory power, simplicity, empirical adequacy, etc.), the first theory meets the criteria bette…Read more
  •  1
    The idea of a social contract has played a major role in modern political philosophy but not in modern epistemology, -- not even in more recent "social theories of knowledge". The idea of an epistemic contract, however, is very interesting and deserves more attention. In this paper, I discuss arguments to the effect that we cannot do without epistemic contracts. I come to the conclusion that these arguments are not convincing. If one wants to make use of contractarian arguments in epistemology, …Read more
  •  137
    Reliabilism—modal, probabilistic or contextualist
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 79 (1): 77-89. 2009.
    This paper discusses two versions of reliabilism: modal and probabilistic reliabilism. Modal reliabilism faces the problem of the missing closeness metric for possible worlds while probalistic reliabilism faces the problem of the relevant reference class. Despite the severity of these problems, reliabilism is still very plausible (also for independent reasons). I propose to stick with reliabilism, propose a contextualist (or, alternatively, harmlessly relativist) solution to the above problems a…Read more
  •  73
    Necessarily Incompatible Consistent Wants
    Acta Analytica 32 (4): 489-490. 2017.
    This paper argues that the wants or desires of a person can be consistent with each other and still necessarily incompatible with each other and for interesting reasons. It is argued here that this problem is not rare and that there is no solution in sight.
  •  114
    Is Knowledge Safe?
    American Philosophical Quarterly 45 (1). 2008.
    One of the most interesting accounts of knowledge which have been recently proposed is the safety account of knowledge. According to it, one only knows that p if one's true belief that p could not have easily been false: S believes that p ==> p (where "==>" stands for the subjunctive conditional). This paper presents a counter-example and discusses attempts to fix the problem. It turns out that there is a deeper underlying problem which does not allow for a solution that would help the safety th…Read more
  •  23
    Epistemic Dimensions of Personhood, by Simon Evnine
    Mind 118 (471): 823-827. 2009.
    Review of Evnine, "Epistemic Dimensions of Personhood".
  •  77
    Varieties of contextualism: Standards and descriptions
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 69 (1): 229-246. 2005.
    Most contextualists agree that contexts differ with respect to relevant epistemic standards. In this paper, I discuss the idea that the difference between more modest and stricter standards should be explained in terms of the closeness or remoteness of relevant possible worlds. I argue that there are serious problems with this version of contextualism. In the second part of the paper, I argue for another form of contextualism that has little to do with standards and a lot with the well-known pro…Read more
  •  122
    Counting on numbers
    Analysis 69 (3): 446-448. 2009.
    1. Here is a very simple game. You come up with a number and I come up with a number. If I come up with the higher number, I win; otherwise you win. You go first. Call this ‘The Very Simple Game’. Few would play it if they had to go first and many if they are guaranteed to go second.2. Here is another one. You come up with a number n and I come up with a number m. If m times 1/ n > 1, then I win; if not, then you win. You go first. Call this ‘Still The Very Simple Game’. Since I win just in case…Read more
  •  120
    Problems for Sinnott-Armstrong's moral contrastivism
    Philosophical Quarterly 58 (232). 2008.
    In his recent book Moral Skepticisms Walter Sinnott-Armstrong argues in great detail for contrastivism with respect to justified moral belief and moral knowledge. I raise three questions concerning this view. First, how would Sinnott-Armstrong account for constraints on admissible contrast classes? Secondly, how would he deal with notorious problems concerning relevant reference classes? Finally, how can he account for basic features of moral agency? It turns out that the last problem is the mos…Read more
  •  128
    Lotteries And Contexts
    Erkenntnis 61 (2): 415-428. 2004.
    There are many ordinary propositions we think we know. Almost every ordinary proposition entails some "lottery proposition" which we think we do not know but to which we assign a high probability of being true (for instance: “I will never be a multi-millionaire” entails “I will not win this lottery”). How is this possible - given that some closure principle is true? This problem, also known as “the Lottery puzzle”, has recently provoked a lot of discussion. In this paper I discuss one of the mos…Read more
  •  34
    Gerhard Ernst: Das problem Des wissens, paderborn: Mentis 2002
    Grazer Philosophische Studien 68 (1): 221-223. 2005.
    Review of Ernst, "Das Problem des Wissens".