University of Notre Dame
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1994
San Diego, California, United States of America
Areas of Specialization
17th/18th Century Philosophy
Areas of Interest
17th/18th Century Philosophy
PhilPapers Editorships
Kant: Causation
  •  1
    Contributors
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. pp. 319-322. 2014.
  •  2
    Index of Names
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. pp. 307-310. 2014.
  • Citations and Abbreviations
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. 2014.
  •  1
    Contents
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. 2014.
  •  1
    Index of Subjects
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. pp. 311-318. 2014.
  •  2
    Bibliography
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. pp. 293-306. 2014.
  • This chapter describes Immanuel Kant's conception of anthropology and the most basic distinctions he draws when invoking faculties throughout the anthropology transcripts. It explains Kant's account of the objective senses (hearing, sight, and touch), and shows that the sensory material provided by these senses are empirical conditions of experience that supplement the a priori conditions articulated in the Critique of Pure Reason. The chapter also describes some of the central details of Kant's…Read more
  • Introduction
    In Kant and the Sciences, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  • Kant on Rational Cosmology
    In Kant and the Sciences, Oxford University Press. 2001.
    This paper discusses Kant’s acceptance of four principles of rational cosmology: the principles of no fate, no chance, no leap, and no gap. It argues that these principles are neither purely analytic nor identical to the epistemological principles of the first Critique. Rather, they represent genuine, distinctively ontological principles that underlie the principles of empirical cosmology, which would be discovered empirically. This interpretation suggests that for Kant, philosophy is not govern…Read more
  •  10
  •  9
    18 The Antinomy of Pure Reason, Sections 3–8
    In Georg Mohr & Marcus Willaschek (eds.), Immanuel Kant: Kritik der reinen Vernunft, De Gruyter. pp. 355-370. 2024.
  •  20
    : In a short and much-neglected passage in the second Critique, Kant discusses the threat posed to human freedom by theological determinism. In this paper we present an interpretation of Kant’s conception of and response to this threat. Regarding his conception, we argue that he addresses two versions of the threat: either God causes appearances directly or he does so indirectly by causing things in themselves which in turn cause appearances. Kant’s response to the first version is that God cann…Read more
  •  17
    The Development of Physical Influx In Early Eighteenth-Century Germany
    Review of Metaphysics 49 (2): 295-339. 1995.
    Before the story can be told, however, some stage-setting is necessary. First, it is important to be clear about the most basic doctrines of Pre-established Harmony, Occasionalism, and Physical Influx. Physical Influx asserts intersubstantial causation amongst finite substances. For instance, when I appear to kick a ball, I really am the cause of the ball's motion. Pre-established Harmony denies intersubstantial causation, but affirms intrasubstantial causation. According to Pre-established Harm…Read more
  •  9
    18. The Antinomy of Pure Reason, Sections 3–8
    In Georg Mohr & Marcus Willaschek (eds.), Immanuel Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Peeters Press. pp. 447-464. 1999.
  •  169
    Kant on cognition and knowledge
    Synthese 197 (8): 3195-3213. 2020.
    Even though Kant’s theory of cognition (Erkenntnis) is central to his Critique of Pure Reason, it has rarely been asked what exactly Kant means by the term “cognition”. Against the widespread assumption that cognition (in the most relevant sense of that term) can be identified with knowledge or if not, that knowledge is at least a species of cognition, we argue that the concepts of cognition and knowledge in Kant are not only distinct, but even disjunct. To show this, we first (I) investigate Ka…Read more
  •  3
    Kant’s Compatibilism (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 31 (2): 147-149. 1999.
  •  12
    Book Notes (review)
    with Nora K. Bell, Samantha J. Brennan, William F. Bristow, Diana H. Coole, Justin DArms, Michael S. Davis, Daniel A. Dombrowski, John J. P. Donnelly, Anthony J. Ellis, Mark C. Fowler, Alan E. Fuchs, Chris Hackler, Garth L. Hallett, Rita C. Manning, Kevin E. Olson, Lansing R. Pollock, Marc Lee Raphael, Robert A. Sedler, Charlene Haddock Seigfried, Kristin S. Schrader‐Frechette, Anita Silvers, Doran Smolkin, Alan G. Soble, James P. Sterba, and Stephen P. Turner
    Ethics 111 (2): 446-459. 2001.
  •  10
    Kant on the Hiddenness of God
    Kantian Review 14 (1): 81-122. 2009.
    Kant's sustained reflections on God have received considerable scholarly attention over the years and rightly so. His provocative criticisms of the three traditional theoretical proofs of the existence of God, and his own positive proof for belief in God's existence on moral grounds, have fully deserved the clarification and analysis that has occurred in these discussions. What I want to focus on, however, is the extent to which Kant's position contains resources sufficient to answer a line of q…Read more
  •  42
    Kant’s Account of Cognition
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 55 (1): 83-112. 2017.
    kant’s critique of pure reason undertakes a systematic investigation of the possibility of synthetic cognition a priori so as to determine whether this kind of cognition is possible in the case of traditional metaphysics.1 While much scholarly attention has been devoted to the distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments as well as to that between the a priori and the a posteriori, less attention has been devoted to understanding exactly what cognition is for Kant. In particular, it is o…Read more
  •  4
    Kant's Theory of Biology (Introduction)
    with Ina Goy
    In Eric Watkins & Ina Goy (eds.), Kant's Theory of Biology, De Gruyter. pp. 1-22. 2014.
  •  14
  •  24
    Comments on Karin de Boer’s Kant’s Reform of Metaphysics
    Kantian Review 27 (1): 133-138. 2022.
    In my comments on Karin de Boer’s Kant’s Reform of Metaphysics, I pose five questions. First, I ask how the fundamental principle of practical philosophy that Kant identifies and claims is fundamentally different from Wolff’s is consistent with the claim that Kant is reforming Wolff’s metaphysics. Second, I ask whether De Boer thinks that Kant, as a reformer of Wolff, continues to accept the Principle of Sufficient Reason (or some variant thereof). Third, I ask whether De Boer accepts Wolff’s co…Read more
  • Autonomy and the Legislation of Laws in the Prolegomena (1783)
    In Stefano Bacin & Oliver Sensen (eds.), The Emergence of Autonomy in Kant’s Moral Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. pp. 122-140. 2018.
    This paper attempts to shed light on Kant’s notion of autonomy in his moral philosophy by considering the extent to which he presents a similar doctrine in his theoretical philosophy, where he strikingly claims (e.g., in the Prolegomena) that the understanding prescribes laws to nature. It argues that even though there are important points of difference between the cases of theoretical legislation of the laws of nature and autonomy in moral philosophy, their extensive parallels make a strong, ev…Read more
  •  42
    Mini-symposium on Kant and cognition
    Synthese 197 (8): 3193-3194. 2020.