•  89
    Perfect Goodness
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. forthcoming.
  •  127
    Restricted Theological Voluntarism
    Philosophy Compass 7 (10): 679-690. 2012.
    In addressing objections to the theological voluntarist program, the consensus response by defenders of theological voluntarism has been to affirm a restricted theological voluntarism on which some, but not all, important normative statuses are to be explained by immediate appeal to the divine will. The aim of this article is to assess the merits and demerits of this restricted view. While affirming the restricted view does free theological voluntarism from certain objections, it comes at the co…Read more
  •  43
    Hobbes on Tacit Covenants
    Hobbes Studies 7 (1): 69-94. 1994.
    Tacit consent theories of political obligation have fallen into disfavor. The difficulties that plague such accounts have been well-known since Hume's "Of the Original Contract"1 and have recently been forcefully reformulated by M. B. E. Smith, A. John Simmons, and Joseph Raz.2 In this article, though, I shall argue that Hobbes' version of the argument from tacit consent escapes the criticisms leveled by Hume, Smith, Simmons, and Raz against tacit consent theories as a class. Crucial to my defen…Read more
  •  42
    Functioning and Flourishing
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 73 193-206. 1999.
  •  54
    Morality and divine authority
    In Thomas P. Flint & Michael Rea (eds.), The Oxford handbook of philosophical theology, Oxford University Press. 2008.
    This article examines morality and divine authority in the context of the question of whether God – that is, God's existence, nature, or activity – explains morality. It begins with some clarifying remarks about the meaning of ‘God’, ‘morality’, and ‘explains’. The article then evaluates the Theistic Explanation of Morality: for every moral fact, there is some fact about God that explains it. Defences of this thesis might appeal to rather different sorts of relationship between moral and theisti…Read more
  •  252
    Divine Command, Divine Will, and Moral Obligation
    Faith and Philosophy 15 (1): 3-27. 1998.
    In this article I consider the respective merits of three interpretations of divine command theory. On DCT1, S’s being morally obligated to φ depends on God’s command that S φ; on DCT2, that moral obligation depends on God’s willing that S be morally obligated to φ; on DCT3, that moral obligation depends on God’s willing that S φ. I argue that the positive reasons that have been brought forward in favor of DCT1 have implications theists would find disturbing and that the positive reasons brought…Read more
  • Alasdair Macintyre (edited book)
    Cambridge University Press. 2003.
    The contribution to contemporary philosophy of Alasdair MacIntyre is enormous. His writings on ethics, political philosophy, philosophy of religion, philosophy of the social sciences and the history of philosophy have established him as one of the philosophical giants of the last fifty years. His best-known book, After Virtue, spurred the profound revival of virtue ethics. Moreover, MacIntyre, unlike so many of his contemporaries, has exerted a deep influence beyond the bourns of academic philos…Read more
  •  42
    Reply to Almeida
    Religious Studies 40 (3): 335-339. 2004.
    Michael J. Almeida offers two criticisms of the argument of my ‘A trilemma for divine command theory’. The first criticism is that I mistakenly assume the validity of the following inference pattern: property A is identical to property B; property B supervenes on property C; therefore, property A supervenes on property C. The second criticism is that I have misinterpreted the moral-supervenience thesis upon which I rely in making this argument. The first of Almeida's criticisms is completely unt…Read more
  •  209
    Not Penal Substitution but Vicarious Punishment
    Faith and Philosophy 26 (3): 253-273. 2009.
    The penal substitution account of the Atonement fails for conceptual reasons: punishment is expressive action, condemning the party punished, and so is not transferable from a guilty to an innocent party. But there is a relative to the penal substitution view, the vicarious punishment account, that is neither conceptually nor morally objectionable. On this view, the guilty person’s punishment consists in the suffering of an innocent to whom he or she bears a special relationship. Sinful humanity…Read more
  •  6
    Hobbes' Shortsightedness Account of Conflict
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 31 (2): 239-253. 2010.
  •  4
    From the Editor
    Faith and Philosophy 33 (1): 3-4. 2016.
  •  79
    Divine authority and divine perfection
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 49 (3): 155-177. 2001.
  •  88
    The Conscience Principle
    Journal of Philosophical Research 22 387-407. 1997.
    My aim is to defend the conscience principle: One ought never to act against the dictates of one’s conscience. In the first part of this paper, I explain what I mean by “conscience” and “dictate of conscience,” and I show that the notion that the conscience principle is inherently anti-authoritarian or inherently fanatical is mistaken. In the second part, I argue that the existence of mistaken conscience does not reduce the conscience principle to absurdity. In the third part, I present two argu…Read more
  •  34
    Philosophy of law
    Blackwell. 2007.
    The Philosophy of Law is a broad-reaching text that guides readers through the basic analytical and normative issues in the field, highlighting key historical and contemporary thinkers and offering a unified treatment of the various issues in the philosophy of law. Enlivened with numerous, everyday examples to illustrate various concepts of law. Employs the idea of three central commonplaces about law - that law is a social matter, that law is authoritative, and that law is for the common good -…Read more
  •  59
    Hobbes on the Evil of Death
    Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 82 (1): 36-61. 2000.
  •  36
    Dancy, Jonathan. Practical Reality (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 55 (2): 388-390. 2001.
  •  64
    Self-Evidence, Human Nature, and Natural Law
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 69 (3): 471-484. 1995.
  •  28
    Philosophical Anarchism and Legal Indifference
    American Philosophical Quarterly 32 (2). 1995.
  •  79
    Natural Law and Practical Rationality
    Cambridge University Press. 2001.
    Natural law theory has been undergoing a revival, especially in political philosophy and jurisprudence. Yet, most fundamentally, natural law theory is not a political theory, but a moral theory, or more accurately a theory of practical rationality. According to the natural law account of practical rationality, the basic reasons for actions are basic goods that are grounded in the nature of human beings. Practical rationality aims to identify and characterize reasons for action and to explain how…Read more
  •  128
    Does God's existence make a difference to how we explain morality? Mark C. Murphy critiques the two dominant theistic accounts of morality--natural law theory and divine command theory--and presents a novel third view. He argues that we can value natural facts about humans and their good, while keeping God at the centre of our moral explanations.
  •  191
    The simple desire-fulfillment theory
    Noûs 33 (2): 247-272. 1999.
    It seems to be a widely shared view that any defensible desire-fulfillment theory of welfare must be framed not in terms of what an agent, in fact, desires but rather in terms of what an agent would desire under hypothetical conditions that include improved information. Unfortunately, though, such accounts are subject to serious criticisms. In this paper I show that in the face of these criticisms the best response is to jettison any appeal to idealized information conditions: the considerations…Read more
  •  25
    Desire and Ethics in Hobbes's Leviathan : A Response to Professor Deigh
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 38 (2): 259-268. 2000.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:Desire and Ethics in Hobbes's Leviathan:A Response to Professor DeighAccording to the "orthodox" interpretation of Hobbes's ethics, the laws of nature are the products of means-end thinking. According to the "definitivist" interpretation recently offered by John Deigh, the laws of nature are generated by reason operating on a definition of "law of nature," where the content of this definition is given by linguistic usage.2 I aim to a…Read more
  •  9
    Philosophy of Law: The Fundamentals
    Wiley-Blackwell. 2006.
    _The Philosophy of Law_ is a broad-reaching text that guides readers through the basic analytical and normative issues in the field, highlighting key historical and contemporary thinkers and offering a unified treatment of the various issues in the philosophy of law. Enlivened with numerous, everyday examples to illustrate various concepts of law. Employs the idea of three central commonplaces about law - that law is a social matter, that law is authoritative, and that law is for the common good…Read more