•  25
    This chapter investigates the idea of collective epistemic commonality suggested by Charles Taylor's example, and contrasts it with a distributive notion of epistemic commonality. It describes a number of accounts of collective epistemic commonality, and then argues that, contrary to what Taylor suggests, conversation is not constitutive of collective epistemic commonality as such, but rather presupposes basic forms of collective epistemic commonality. Taylor's remarks indicate that understandin…Read more
  •  4
    Otfried Höffes transzendental-anthropologische Menschenrechtsbegründung
    Archiv für Rechts- Und Sozialphilosophie 81 (4). 1995.
  •  247
    Plural self-awareness
    Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 13 (1): 7-24. 2014.
    It has been claimed in the literature that collective intentionality and group attitudes presuppose some “sense of ‘us’” among the participants (other labels sometimes used are “sense of community,” “communal awareness,” “shared point of view,” or “we-perspective”). While this seems plausible enough on an intuitive level, little attention has been paid so far to the question of what the nature and role of this mysterious “sense of ‘us’” might be. This paper states (and argues for) the following …Read more
  •  36
    ‘Nostrism’: Social Identities in Experimental Games
    Analyse & Kritik 27 (1): 172-187. 2005.
    In this paper it is argued that a) altruism is an inadequate label for human cooperative behavior, and b) an adequate account of cooperation has to depart from the standard economic model of human behavior by taking note of the agents' capacity to see themselves and act as team-members. Contrary to what Fehr et al. seem to think, the main problem of the conceptual limitations of the standard model is not so much the assumption of sel shness but rather the atomistic conception of the individual. …Read more
  •  38
    Plural Action
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 38 (1): 25-54. 2008.
    In this paper, I distinguish three claims, which I label individual intentional autonomy, individual intentional autarky, and intentional individualism. The autonomy claim is that under normal circumstances, each individual's behavior has to be interpreted as his or her own action. The autarky claim is that the intentional interpretation of an individual's behavior has to bottom out in that individual's own volitions, or pro-attitudes. The individualism claim is weaker, arguing that any interpre…Read more
  •  12
  •  21
    Neue Wohlfahrtsphilosophie
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 54 (6): 969-972. 2006.
  •  223
    Philosophical egoism: Its nature and limitations
    Economics and Philosophy 26 (2): 217-240. 2010.
    Egoism and altruism are unequal contenders in the explanation of human behaviour. While egoism tends to be viewed as natural and unproblematic, altruism has always been treated with suspicion, and it has often been argued that apparent cases of altruistic behaviour might really just be some special form of egoism. The reason for this is that egoism fits into our usual theoretical views of human behaviour in a way that altruism does not. This is true on the biological level, where an evolutionary…Read more
  •  9
    Introduction
    with Christoph Henning and Dieter Thomä
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 1-6. 2014.
  •  21
    Heidegger and the ‘Cartesian Brainwash’—Towards a Non-Individualistic Account of ‘Dasein’
    Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 35 (2): 132-156. 2004.
  •  10
    Notes on Contributors
    with Christoph Henning and Dieter Thomä
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 225-228. 2014.
  •  9
    Index of Persons
    with Christoph Henning and Dieter Thomä
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 229-230. 2014.
  • “Lebenswelt” zwischen Universalismus und Relativismus.
    Schweizerische Zeitschrift für Soziologie 22. 1996.
  •  26
    Introduction
    Journal of Social Philosophy 49 (1): 7-11. 2018.
  •  10
    Index of Subjects
    with Christoph Henning and Dieter Thomä
    In Hans Bernhard Schmid, Christoph Henning & Dieter Thomä (eds.), Social Capital, Social Identities: From Ownership to Belonging, De Gruyter. pp. 231-234. 2014.
  •  6
    Holding random collections collectively responsible: An introduction
    Filozofija I Društvo 28 (4): 997-1034. 2017.
    nema nema
  •  18
    Ist Vertrauenswürdigkeit das formale Objekt des Vertrauens?
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 64 (1): 89-102. 2016.
    Name der Zeitschrift: Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie Jahrgang: 64 Heft: 1 Seiten: 89-102
  •  1
    Heidegger and the ‚Cartesian Brainwash‘. Towards a Non-Individualistic Account of ‚Dasein‘
    ‘. Journal of the British Society for Phenomenology 35 (2): 132-156. 2004.
  •  11
    Mitleid in der Moralphilosophie
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 53 (2). 2005.
  •  18
    Editorial Note
    Journal of Social Ontology 1 (1). 2015.
    Social Ontology encompasses a wide variety of inquiries into the nature, structure and perhaps essence of social phenomena, and their role and place in our world. Topics of research in Social Ontology range from small-scale interactions to large-scale institutions, from spontaneous teamwork to the functioning of formal organizations, and from unintended consequences to institutional design. Social Ontology brings together theoretical work from a large number of disciplines. This rapidly evolving…Read more
  •  183
    Collective Intentionality
    Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2012.
  • Evolution by Imitation. Gabriel Tarde and the Memetic Project
    Distinction. Scandinavian Journal for Social Theory 9. 2004.
  •  69
    Expressing Group Attitudes: On First Person Plural Authority
    Erkenntnis 79 (S9): 1685-1701. 2014.
    Under normal circumstances, saying that you have a thought, a belief, a desire, or an intention differs from saying that somebody (who happens to be you) has that attitude. The former statement comes with some form of first person authority and constitutes commitments that are not involved in the latter case. Speaking with first person authority, and thereby publicly committing oneself, is a practice that plays an important role in our communication and in our understanding of what it means to b…Read more
  •  68
    Collective Epistemology (edited book)
    Ontos. 2011.
    The aim of this volume is to examine this claim, and to place it in the wider context of recent epistemological debates about the role of sociality in knowledge acquisition.
  •  13
    Das Böse an Augustinus’ Birnendiebstahl
    Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie 67 (4): 517-538. 2019.
    In the second book of theConfessions, Augustine flabbergasts his interpreters by exaggerating an adolescent escapade (a pear theft) and making it a monstrosity. He conjectures that the pear thieves might have commited the theft purely for the sake of thieving, and thus, that they displayed a kind of evil that is not even presented by the arch-villain of Ciceronian antiquity, the conspirer Catilina. Following Aquinas’ interpretation this comparison has been considered a reductio in most of the re…Read more