•  19
    The Irreducibility of Knowledge
    Logique Et Analyse 77 (Sommaire): 167-176. 1977.
    In this article it is argued that it is impossible to give a reductive analysis of knowledge, given that knowledge is an "epistemic" concept with these marks: (1) like necessity, it is only partially truth-functional; and, (2) unlike necessity, it includes an "intentional" component (belief) which is completely non-truth-functional. a reductive analysis would have to contain at least one extensional component, one intentional component, and none that is itself epistemic. but any plausible analys…Read more
  •  48
    Abortion and the Right to Life
    Social Theory and Practice 3 (Fall): 381-401. 1975.
  •  54
    The impossibility of massive error
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 405-409. 1993.
    I argue that Davidson's anti-skeptical thesis can survive objections made against it by treating skepticism as logically possible, but not epistemically possible. That is, the skeptical hypothesis of massive error conflicts with what we must take ourselves to know if we are to have coherent thought and speech.
  •  45
  •  95
    How to define a nonskeptical fallibilism
    Philosophia 22 (3-4): 361-372. 1993.
  •  16
    Abortion and the Right to Life
    Social Theory and Practice 3 (4): 381-401. 1975.
  •  90
    Free will and intentional action
    Philosophia 16 (3-4): 355-364. 1986.
    I argue for the following analysis of a freely willed action: an act is done of one's own free will, if and only if, it is an intentional act performed by one acting as a rational agent from unobstructed reasons, and so situated that he or she has the capacity to forbear from performing it.
  •  42
    The time-gap argument
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (3): 263-272. 1969.
    I argue that the time-gap argument poses no objection to Direct Realism. In the case of exploded stars many light years from us, what we see is no longer the star, but its light. I argue that in all cases of seeing we see light, but only when physical objects exist at the time of our seeing do we see them.
  •  243
    Skepticism made certain
    Journal of Philosophy 71 (5): 140-150. 1974.
  • Definitions and disembodied minds
    Personalist Forum 55 (4): 334-43. 1974.
  •  56
    Time-gap myopia
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 50 (1): 55-57. 1972.
    I answer objections to my article, "The Time-Gap Argument," made by C. Daniels in his "Seeing Through a Time Gap."
  •  112
    Aristotelian materialism
    Philosophia 34 (3): 253-266. 2006.
    I argue that a modern gloss on Aristotle’s notions of Form and Matter not only allows us to escape a dualism of the psychological and the physical, but also results in a plausible sort of materialism. This is because Aristotle held that the essential nature of any psychological state, including perception and human thought, is to be some physical property. I also show that Hilary Putnam and Martha Nussbaum are mistaken in saying that Aristotle was not a materialist, but a functionalist. His func…Read more
  •  14
    The Impossibility of Massive Error
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 405-409. 1993.
  • Skepticism about Epistemic Reasons
    Iyyun, The Jerusalem Philosophical Quarterly 44 (July): 273-292. 1995.