•  53
    An analysis of empirical knowledge
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 9 (1): 3-11. 1971.
  •  37
    Perception and Animal Belief
    Philosophy 55 (212). 1980.
    I argue that sentences ascribing beliefs to non-human animals have the same logical form as sentences of the "perceives that" variety. Pace D.M. Armstrong, I argue that animal belief sentences can be referentially opaque, just as perception sentences containing a propositional clause are. In both cases, referential opacity requires our assuming that the animal believer and the human perceiver has each identified the object of the belief or perception.
  •  26
    Skepticism Disarmed
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 13 (1). 1983.
    If skepticism is once again fashionable, then much of the credit must go to Peter Unger who gives a sustained defense of an ultra-pyrrhonian position in his book, Ignorance: A case for Skepticism. Starting with a version of the traditional argument that we know nothing about the external world, Unger plunges deeper into skeptical waters by next arguing that there is at most hardly anything which we know to be so; and he scarcely pauses before proceeding to defend the stronger conclusion of ‘univ…Read more
  •  58
    Out-Gunning Skepticism
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (3). 1987.
    Bredo C. Johnsen1 misconceives my strictures concerning acceptance of the following principle : If A both knows that p and knows that p entails q, then A can come to know that q.Johnsen seems unaware that my criticism was intended to apply only after is made to appear in its most plausible light; that is, only after its consequent is interpreted as: ’It is logically possible for A to know that q.’ Without this interpretation might be dismissed simply on the grounds that A suffers from some physi…Read more
  •  5
    Critical Review: Thought (review)
    Journal of Critical Analysis 5 (4): 146-150. 1975.
  •  17
    The Irreducibility of Knowledge
    Logique Et Analyse 77 (Sommaire): 167-176. 1977.
    In this article it is argued that it is impossible to give a reductive analysis of knowledge, given that knowledge is an "epistemic" concept with these marks: (1) like necessity, it is only partially truth-functional; and, (2) unlike necessity, it includes an "intentional" component (belief) which is completely non-truth-functional. a reductive analysis would have to contain at least one extensional component, one intentional component, and none that is itself epistemic. but any plausible analys…Read more
  •  48
    The impossibility of massive error
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 53 (2): 405-409. 1993.
    I argue that Davidson's anti-skeptical thesis can survive objections made against it by treating skepticism as logically possible, but not epistemically possible. That is, the skeptical hypothesis of massive error conflicts with what we must take ourselves to know if we are to have coherent thought and speech.
  •  44
    Abortion and the Right to Life
    Social Theory and Practice 3 (Fall): 381-401. 1975.
  •  43
  •  94
    How to define a nonskeptical fallibilism
    Philosophia 22 (3-4): 361-372. 1993.
  •  11
    Abortion and the Right to Life
    Social Theory and Practice 3 (4): 381-401. 1975.
  •  66
    The time-gap argument
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 47 (3): 263-272. 1969.
    I argue that the time-gap argument poses no objection to Direct Realism. In the case of exploded stars many light years from us, what we see is no longer the star, but its light. I argue that in all cases of seeing we see light, but only when physical objects exist at the time of our seeing do we see them.
  •  88
    Free will and intentional action
    Philosophia 16 (3-4): 355-364. 1986.
    I argue for the following analysis of a freely willed action: an act is done of one's own free will, if and only if, it is an intentional act performed by one acting as a rational agent from unobstructed reasons, and so situated that he or she has the capacity to forbear from performing it.