•  253
  •  285
    Few can imagine a world without telephones or televisions; many depend on computers and the Internet as part of daily life. Without scientific theory, these developments would not have been possible. In this exceptionally clear and engaging introduction to philosophy of science, James Ladyman explores the philosophical questions that arise when we reflect on the nature of the scientific method and the knowledge it produces. He discusses whether fundamental philosophical questions about knowledge…Read more
  •  44
    Semantic perspective on idealization in quantum mechanics
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 63 51-74. 1998.
  •  821
    Structural Realism
    In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, The Metaphysics Research Lab. 2014.
    Structural realism is considered by many realists and antirealists alike as the most defensible form of scientific realism. There are now many forms of structural realism and an extensive literature about them. There are interesting connections with debates in metaphysics, philosophy of physics and philosophy of mathematics. This entry is intended to be a comprehensive survey of the field.
  •  341
    The primacy of physics generates a philosophical problem that the naturalist must solve in order to be entitled to an egalitarian acceptance of the ontological commitments he or she inherits from the special sciences and fundamental physics. The problem is the generalized causal exclusion argument. If there is no genuine causation in the domains of the special sciences but only in fundamental physics then there are grounds for doubting the existence of macroscopic objects and properties, or at l…Read more
  •  46
    Review of Naturalizing Epistemology by Fred D’Agostino (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90 (3): 605-608. 2012.
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Volume 90, Issue 3, Page 605-608, September 2012
  •  58
    Whether we think of the routine conviction or acquittal of suspects on the basis of scientific evidence in the law courts, the trust placed in scientific medicine and the extraordinary interventions it makes possible, or the importance that policy makers attach to the opinions of scientists, it is clear that those making up our scientific institutions are among the most authoritative and respected people that there are. Among intellectual endeavours science has an unrivalled dominance in terms o…Read more
  •  1904
    What is structural realism?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 29 (3): 409-424. 1998.
  •  29
    Beyond a joke (review)
    The Philosophers' Magazine 42 105-107. 2008.
  •  611
    The principle of the identity of indiscernibles and quantum mechanics
    Philosophy of Science 77 (1): 117-136. 2010.
    It is argued that recent discussion of the principle of the identity of indiscernibles (PII) and quantum mechanics has lost sight of the broader philosophical motivation and significance of PII and that the `received view' of the status of PII in the light of quantum mechanics survives recent criticisms of it by Muller, Saunders, and Seevinck.
  •  615
    We outline Ladyman's 'metaphysical' or 'ontic' form of structuralrealism and defend it against various objections. Cao, in particular, has questioned theview of ontology presupposed by this approach and we argue that by reconceptualisingobjects in structural terms it offers the best hope for the realist in thecontext of modern physics.
  •  30
    Review (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (3): 487-490. 1996.
  •  235
    Does Physics Answer Metaphysical Questions?
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 61 179-201. 2007.
    According to logical positivism, so the story goes, metaphysical questions are meaningless, since they do not admit of empirical confirmation or refutation. However, the logical positivists did not in fact reject as meaningless all questions about for example, the structure of space and time. Rather, key figures such as Reichenbach and Schlick believed that scientific theories often presupposed a conceptual framework that was not itself empirically testable, but which was required for the theory…Read more
  •  386
    Physicalism, supervenience and the fundamental level
    with Robin Brown
    Philosophical Quarterly 59 (234): 20-38. 2009.
    We provide a formulation of physicalism, and show that this is to be favoured over alternative formulations. Much of the literature on physicalism assumes without argument that there is a fundamental level to reality, and we show that a consideration of the levels problem and its implications for physicalism tells in favour of the form of physicalism proposed here. Its hey elements are, fast, that the empirical and substantive part of physicalism amounts to a prediction that physics will not pos…Read more
  •  694
    The aim of this paper is to revisit the phlogiston theory to see what can be learned from it about the relationship between scientific realism, approximate truth and successful reference. It is argued that phlogiston theory did to some extent correctly describe the causal or nomological structure of the world, and that some of its central terms can be regarded as referring. However, it is concluded that the issue of whether or not theoretical terms successfully refer is not the key to formulatin…Read more
  •  82
    Big data
    The Philosophers' Magazine 72 69-70. 2016.
    [no abstract]
  •  322
    Abstractvan Fraassen (The empirical stance, 2002) contrasts the empirical stance with the materialist stance. The way he describes them makes both of them attractive, and while opposed they have something in common for both stances are scientific approaches to philosophy. The difference between them reflects their differing conceptions of science itself. Empiricists emphasise fallibilism, verifiability and falsifiability, and also to some extent scepticism and tolerance of novel hypotheses. Mate…Read more
  •  311
    Reinflating the semantic approach
    International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 13 (2). 1999.
    The semantic, or model-theoretic, approach to theories has recently come under criticism on two fronts: (i) it is claimed that it cannot account for the wide diversity of models employed in scientific practice—a claim which has led some to propose a “deflationary” account of models; (ii) it is further contended that the sense of “model” used by the approach differs from that given in model theory. Our aim in the present work is to articulate a possible response to these claims, drawing on recent…Read more
  •  1529
    There is good reason to believe that scientific realism requires a commitment to the objective modal structure of the physical world. Causality, equilibrium, laws of nature, and probability all feature prominently in scientific theory and explanation, and each one is a modal notion. If we are committed to the content of our best scientific theories, we must accept the modal nature of the physical world. But what does the scientific realist’s commitment to physical modality require? We consider w…Read more
  •  62
    Supervenience: Not local and not two-way
    Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27 (5): 630-630. 2004.
    This commentary argues that Ross & Spurrett (R&S) have not shown that supervenience is two-way, but they have shown that all the sciences, including physics, make use of functional and supervenient properties. The entrenched defender of Kim's position could insist that only fundamental physics describes causal relations directly, but Kim's microphysical reductionism becomes completely implausible when we consider contemporary physics.
  •  30
    Review: Discussion: Empiricism versus Metaphysics (review)
    Philosophical Studies 121 (2). 2004.
  •  5
    Editorial
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 56 (1): 1-2. 2005.
  •  456
    What is a complex system?
    with James Lambert and Karoline Wiesner
    European Journal for Philosophy of Science 3 (1): 33-67. 2013.
    Complex systems research is becoming ever more important in both the natural and social sciences. It is commonly implied that there is such a thing as a complex system, different examples of which are studied across many disciplines. However, there is no concise definition of a complex system, let alone a definition on which all scientists agree. We review various attempts to characterize a complex system, and consider a core set of features that are widely associated with complex systems in the…Read more
  •  117
    A field guide to the Higgs
    The Philosophers' Magazine 59 (59): 21-22. 2012.