Cambridge, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  3
    Review of L. Jonathan Cohen: The Implications of Induction (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 22 (2): 202-205. 1971.
  •  363
    Is objective moral justification possible on a quasi-realist foundation?
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (2). 1999.
    This essay juxtaposes the position in metaethics defended, expressivism with quasirealistic trimmings, with the ancient problem of relativism. It argues that, perhaps surprisingly, there is less of a problem of normative truth on this approach than on others. Because ethics is not in the business of representing aspects of the world, there is no way to argue for a plurality of moral truths, simply from the existence of a plurality of moral opinions. The essay also argues that other approaches, w…Read more
  • Philosophical Logic
    Open University Press. 1980.
  •  43
    Being good: an introduction to ethics
    Oxford University Press. 2001.
    From political scandals at the highest levels to inflated repair bills at the local garage, we are seemingly surrounded with unethical behavior, so why should we behave any differently? Why should we go through life anchored down by rules no one else seems to follow? Writing with wit and elegance, Simon Blackburn tackles such questions in this lively look at ethics, highlighting the complications and doubts and troubling issues that spring from the very simple question of how we ought to live. B…Read more
  •  167
    In this paper I contemplate two phenomena that have impressed theorists concerned with the domain of reasons and of normativity. One is the much-discussed ‘externality’ of reasons. Reasons are just there, anyway. They exist whether or not agents take any notice of them. They do not only exist in the light of contingent desires or mere inclinations. They are ‘external’ not ‘internal’. They bear on us, even when through ignorance or wickedness we take no notice of them. They thus very conspicuousl…Read more
  •  13
    The Inaugural Address: Paradise Regained
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 79. 2005.
    In this paper I consider some of the vicissitudes that the epistemology of the empirical world has suffered in the last half-century. I cast doubt on some of the ruling metaphors of the area, and on the flight from empiricism and foundationalism that they have assisted. But I also reject attempts to secure a better epistemology that themselves collaborate with the same fundamental mistakes, and in particular that of a spatial conception of the mind.
  •  79
  •  256
    Hume and thick connexions
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 50 (n/a): 237-250. 1990.
  •  1
    Essays on Quasi-Realism
    Philosophical Quarterly 47 (186): 96-99. 1997.
  •  154
    Justification, Scepticism, and Nihilism
    Utilitas 7 (2): 237. 1995.
    Sinnott-Armstrong's paper principally defends our inability to justify, philosophically, normal moral claims. In particular, we cannot justify them against other claims, especially the claim of moral nihilism. Moral nihilism is the doctrine that there are no moral obligations. This thesis ‘does not lie in meta-ethics. It is a universally quantified substantive moral claim’. Sinnott-Annstrong makes it clear that he does not actually believe this doctrine, but he believes that it is coherent, and …Read more
  • Think. A Compelling Introduction to Philosophy
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 191 (3): 402-403. 2001.
  •  206
    Just causes
    with Nicholas L. Sturgeon
    Philosophical Studies 61 (1-2): 3-42. 1991.
  •  30
    What’s it all about?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 27 20-21. 2004.
  •  60
    Replies
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (1). 2002.
    Dreier’s sympathy with expressivism is welcome, and yet he comes upon an ‘uncomfortable surprise’, in a circularity or regress that he detects in my attempt to place ethical commitments in a natural world. The circularity is that the expressivist analysis of what is going on, when we invoke norms, identifies particular states of mind: valuings, or acceptance of norms, or complexes of attitude. But states of mind are themselves normatively tainted. Hence: ‘the kernel of expressivist analysis invo…Read more
  •  6
    What about Me?
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 60 153-66. 1986.
  •  95
    Paradise regained
    Supplement to the Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 79 (1): 1-14. 2005.
    In this paper I consider some of the vicissitudes that the epistemology of the empirical world has suffered in the last half-century. I cast doubt on some of the ruling metaphors of the area, and on the flight from empiricism and foundationalism that they have assisted. But I also reject attempts to secure a better epistemology that themselves collaborate with the same fundamental mistakes, and in particular that of a spatial conception of the mind
  •  137
    Swinburne on religion and ethics
    Think 7 (20): 17-21. 2008.
    Simon Blackburn responds to the preceding article by Richard Swinburne
  •  48
    The Oxford dictionary of philosophy
    Oxford University Press. 2005.
    This bestselling dictionary is written by one of the leading philosophers of our time, and it is widely recognized as the best dictionary of its kind. Comprehensive and authoritative, it covers every aspect of philosophy from Aristotle to Zen. With clear and concise definitions, it provides lively and accessible coverage of not only Western philosophical traditions, but also themes from Chinese, Indian, Islamic, and Jewish philosophy. New entries on philosophy of economics, social theory, neuros…Read more
  •  405
    Perspectives, fictions, errors, play
    In Brian Leiter & Neil Sinhababu (eds.), Nietzsche and morality, Oxford University Press. pp. 281--96. 2007.