Hallvard Lillehammer

Birkbeck College, University Of London
Birkbeck, University of London
Sheffield, South Yorkshire, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
Areas of Interest
Meta-Ethics
Normative Ethics
  •  695
    Facts, Ends, and Normative Reasons
    The Journal of Ethics 14 (1): 17-26. 2010.
    This paper is about the relationship between two widely accepted and apparently conflicting claims about how we should understand the notion of ‘reason giving’ invoked in theorising about reasons for action. According to the first claim, reasons are given by facts about the situation of agents. According to the second claim, reasons are given by ends. I argue that the apparent conflict between these two claims is less deep than is generally recognised.
  •  464
    The Idea of a Normative Reason
    In Peter Schaber & Rafael Hüntelmann (eds.), Grundlagen der Ethik, De Gruyter. pp. 41--65. 2003.
    Recent work in English speaking moral philosophy has seen the rise to prominence of the idea of a normative reason1. By ‘normative reasons’ I mean the reasons agents appeal to in making rational claims on each other. Normative reasons are good reasons on which agents ought to act, even if they are not actually motivated accordingly2. To this extent, normative reasons are distinguishable from the motivating reasons agents appeal to in reason explanations. Even agents who fail to act on their norm…Read more
  •  464
    Who needs bioethicists?
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 35 (1): 131-144. 2003.
    Recent years have seen the emergence of a new brand of moral philosopher. Straddling the gap between academia on the one hand, and the world of law, medicine, and politics on the other, bioethicists have appeared, offering advice on ethical issues to a wider public than the philosophy classroom. Some bioethicists, like Peter Singer, have achieved wide notoriety in the public realm with provocative arguments that challenge widely held beliefs about the relative moral status of animals, human foet…Read more
  •  7
    Review of Robert Audi, Practical Reasoning and Ethical Decision (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (5). 2006.
  •  623
    The aim of this paper is to trace the development of a particular current of thought known under the label ‘pragmatism’ in the last part of the Twentieth century and the beginning of the Twenty-first. I address three questions about this current of thought. First, what is its actual historical development? Second, does it constitute a single, coherent, philosophical outlook? Third, in what form, if any, does it constitute an attractive philosophical outlook. In the course of addressing these q…Read more
  • Introduction
    In Hallvard Lillehammer & D. H. Mellor (eds.), Ramsey's Legacy, Oxford University Press. 2005.
  •  14
    Consequentialism and Global Ethics
    In Michael Boylan (ed.), The Morality and Global Justice Reader, Westview Press. pp. 89. 2011.
  •  58
    Moral Error Theory: History, Critique, Defence, written by Jonas Olson (review)
    International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 7 (1): 57-61. 2017.
    _ Source: _Page Count 5
  •  66
    Socratic puzzles. Robert Nozick
    Mind 110 (439): 802-806. 2001.
  •  565
    Moral Cognitivism
    Philosophical Papers 31 (1): 1-25. 2002.
    Abstract The paper explicates a set of criteria the joint satisfaction of which is taken to qualify moral judgements as cognitive. The paper examines evidence that some moral judgements meet these criteria, and relates the resulting conception of moral judgements to ongoing controversies about cognitivism in ethics
  • Ramsey's Legacy
    with David Hugh Mellor
    Tijdschrift Voor Filosofie 68 (3): 669-669. 2006.
  •  809
    Constructivism and the Error Theory
    In Christian Miller (ed.), Continuum Companion to Ethics, Continuum. 2011.
    This paper presents a comparative evaluation of constructivist and error theoretic accounts of moral claims. It is argued that constructivism has distinct advantages over error theory
  •  903
    Darwin’s treatment of morality in The Descent of Man has generated a wide variety of responses among moral philosophers. Among these is the dismissal of evolution as irrelevant to ethics by Darwin’s contemporary Henry Sidgwick; the last, and arguably the greatest, of the Nineteenth Century British Utilitarians. This paper offers a re-examination of Sidgwick’s response to evolutionary considerations as irrelevant to ethics and the absence of any engagement with Darwin’s work in Sidgwick’s main et…Read more
  •  33
    From genes to eugenics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C: Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 32 (4): 589-600. 2001.
  •  1379
    Values of Art and the Ethical Question
    British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (4): 376-394. 2008.
    Does the ethical value of a work of art ever contribute to its aesthetic value? I argue that when conventionally interpreted as a request for a conceptual analysis the answer to this question is indeterminate. I then propose a different interpretation of the question on which it is understood as a substantial and normative question internal to the practice of aesthetic criticism.
  •  315
    Analytical dispositionalism and practical reason
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 2 (2): 117-133. 1999.
    The paper examines the plausibility of analytical dispositionalism about practical reason, according to which the following claims are conceptual truths about common sense ethical discourse: i) Ethics: agents have reasons to act in some ways rather than others, and ii) Metaphysical Modesty: there is no such thing as a response independent normative reality. By elucidating two uncontroversial assumptions which are fundamental to the common sense commitment to ethics, I argue that common sense eth…Read more