Stanford University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1993
New York City, New York, United States of America
  •  1
    Phenomenology as rigorous science
    In Brian Leiter & Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford handbook of continental philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Edmund Husserl, the founder of modern phenomenology, always insisted that philosophy is not just a scholarly discipline, but can and must aspire to the status of a ‘strict’ or ‘rigorous science’ (strenge Wissenschaft). Heidegger, by contrast, began his winter lectures in 1929 by dismissing what he called the ‘delusion’ that philosophy was or could be either a discipline or a science as the most disastrous debasement of its innermost essence. To understand what Husserl had in mind, it is importan…Read more
  •  102
    Heidegger’s Temporal Idealism
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (5): 308-312. 2000.
  •  161
    Heidegger's anti-neo-kantianism
    Philosophical Forum 41 (1-2): 131-142. 2010.
  •  40
    The Self after Postmodernity (review)
    Review of Metaphysics 52 (1): 175-177. 1998.
    Calvin Schrag’s Self after Postmodernity is a trim but ambitious book. In it Schrag sets out to correct, or at least to temper—sometimes seemingly to appease—what he regards as the excesses and distortions arising from contemporary assaults on the concepts of selfhood and subjectivity, arising particularly from recent French philosophy. In so doing, he tries to articulate a response to the problem of modernity as framed by Weber and Habermas, that is, in terms of the increasing mutual alienation…Read more
  •  25
    After Modernity: Husserlian Reflections on a Philosophical Tradition (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 59 (2): 550-553. 1999.
    After Modernity is a collection of fifteen short essays, ten of them previously published elsewhere, centering around interpretations of Husserl and applications of his phenomenology to large philosophical problems concerning time and the self. The volume is held together loosely by the author’s answer to the crisis of modernity, a crisis consisting in the apparent hopelessness of grounding norms in superworldly Platonic forms or the rational subject posited by Descartes and Kant. Mensch advocat…Read more
  •  114
    On making sense (and nonsense) of Heidegger
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 63 (3): 561-572. 2001.
    Herman Philipse’s Heidegger’s Philosophy of Being is an attempt to interpret, analyze, and ultimately discredit the whole of Heidegger’s thought. But Philipse’s reading of the texts is uncharitable, and the ideas he presents and criticizes often bear little resemblance to Heidegger’s views. Philipse relies on a crude distinction between “theoretical” and “applicative” interpretations in arguing that Heidegger’s conception of interpretation as a kind of projection is, like the liar’s paradox, for…Read more
  •  1
    Heidegger on Meaning and Practice
    Dissertation, Stanford University. 1993.
    In Being and Time Heidegger advances a critique of Husserl's theory of intentionality by arguing that human understanding consists more fundamentally in an orientation toward practical activity than in mere cognition, for example deliberate perception or judgment. Heidegger criticizes Husserl for importing normative concepts drawn from logic into what purports to be a pure, presuppositionless description of consciousness. Above all, Heidegger is critical of the idealized conception of meaning th…Read more