Stanford University
Department of Philosophy
PhD, 1993
New York City, New York, United States of America
  •  21
    Review of Robert J. Dostal (ed.), The Cambridge Companion to Gadamer (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2002 (10). 2002.
  •  103
    On being social: A reply to Olafson
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 37 (2). 1994.
    Frederick Olafson criticizes Hubert Dreyfus’s interpretation of BEING AND TIME on a number of points, including the meaning of being, the nature of intentionality, and especially the role of das Man in Heidegger’s account of social existence. But on the whole Olafson’s critique is unconvincing because it rests on an implausible account of presence and perceptual intuition in Heidegger’s early philosophy, and because Olafson maintains an overly individuated notion of Dasein and consequently a one…Read more
  •  13
    Heidegger on Correspondence and Correctness
    Graduate Faculty Philosophy Journal 28 (2): 103-116. 2007.
  •  219
    The Body in Husserl and Merleau-Ponty
    Philosophical Topics 27 (2): 205-226. 1999.
    The terminological boxes into which we press the history of philosophy often obscure deep and important differences among major figures supposedly belonging to a single school of thought. One such disparity within the phenomenological movement, often overlooked but by no means invisible, separates Merleau-Pontys Phenomenology of Perception from the Husserlian program that initially inspired it. For Merleau-Pontys phenomenology amounts to a radical, if discreet, departure not only from Husserls t…Read more
  •  1
    Phenomenology as rigorous science
    In Brian Leiter & Michael Rosen (eds.), The Oxford handbook of continental philosophy, Oxford University Press. 2007.
    Edmund Husserl, the founder of modern phenomenology, always insisted that philosophy is not just a scholarly discipline, but can and must aspire to the status of a ‘strict’ or ‘rigorous science’ (strenge Wissenschaft). Heidegger, by contrast, began his winter lectures in 1929 by dismissing what he called the ‘delusion’ that philosophy was or could be either a discipline or a science as the most disastrous debasement of its innermost essence. To understand what Husserl had in mind, it is importan…Read more
  •  101
    Heidegger’s Temporal Idealism
    Journal of Philosophy 97 (5): 308-312. 2000.
  •  154
    Heidegger's anti-neo-kantianism
    Philosophical Forum 41 (1-2): 131-142. 2010.