•  4
    Kant’s Intuitionism (review)
    Philosophical Review 107 (1): 155-158. 1998.
    Wonderfully clear, scholarly, and well argued, Kant’s Intuitionism offers a bold new interpretation of the thesis of the Transcendental Aesthetic. Falkenstein reads Kant as a “formal intuitionist.” That is, he takes Kant to have maintained that the forms of intuition, space, and time were given along with sensations. They were neither preexisting representations, nor intellectual or imaginative constructions out of sensations. In this context “given” contrasts with “constructed”; subjects’ repre…Read more
  • The Problem of Personal Identity
    Dissertation, Princeton University. 1974.
  •  222
    Marr’s Computational Theory of Vision
    Philosophy of Science 55 (March): 1-24. 1988.
    David Marr's theory of vision has been widely cited by philosophers and psychologists. I have three projects in this paper. First, I try to offer a perspicuous characterization of Marr's theory. Next, I consider the implications of Marr's work for some currently popular philosophies of psychology, specifically, the "hegemony of neurophysiology view", the theories of Jerry Fodor, Daniel Dennett, and Stephen Stich, and the view that perception is permeated by belief. In the last section, I conside…Read more
  •  174
    Narrow taxonomy and wide functionalism
    Philosophy of Science 52 (March): 78-97. 1985.
    Three recent, influential critiques (Stich 1978; Fodor 1981c; Block 1980) have argued that various tasks on the agenda for computational psychology put conflicting pressures on its theoretical constructs. Unless something is done, the inevitable result will be confusion or outright incoherence. Stich, Fodor, and Block present different versions of this worry and each proposes a different remedy. Stich wants the central notion of belief to be jettisoned if it cannot be shown to be sound. Fodor tr…Read more
  •  3
    Reasoning in a Subtle World
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 30 (S1): 187-195. 1992.
  •  11
    Discussion: How to reduce a functional psychology?
    Philosophy of Science 47 (March): 134-140. 1980.
  •  19
    On Interpreting Kant’s Thinker as Wittgenstein’s ‘I’
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 61 (1): 33-63. 2000.
    Although both Kant and Wittgenstein made claims about the “unknowability” of cognitive subjects, the current practice of assimilating their positions is mistaken. I argue that Allison’s attempt to understand the Kantian self through the early Wittgenstein and McDowell’s linking of Kant and the later Wittgenstein distort rather than illuminate. Against McDowell, I argue further that the Critique’s analysis of the necessary conditions for cognition produces an account of the sources of epistemic n…Read more
  •  53
    «Kant's Thinker». An Exposition
    Rivista di Filosofia 104 (1): 24-50. 2013.
    Kant's discussion of the relations between cognition and self-consciousness lie at the heart of the Critique of Pure Reason, in the celebrated transcendental deduction. Although this section of Kant's masterpiece is widely believed to contain important insights into cognition and self-consciousness, it has long been viewed as unusually obscure. Many philosophers have tried to avoid the transcendental psychology that Kant employed. By contrast, Patricia Kitcher follows Kant's careful delineation …Read more
  •  13
    Arguing for Apperception
    In Stefano Bacin, Alfredo Ferrarin, Claudio La Rocca & Margit Ruffing (eds.), Kant und die Philosophie in weltbürgerlicher Absicht. Akten des XI. Internationalen Kant-Kongresses, De Gruyter. pp. 189-198. 2013.
  •  25
    Kant on Self-Consciousness
    Philosophical Review 108 (3): 345-386. 1999.
    The highest principle of Kant’s theoretical philosophy is that all cognition must “be combined in one single self-consciousness”. Elsewhere I have tried to explain why he believed that all cognition must belong to a single self ; here I try to clarify the other half of the doctrine. What led him to the claim that all cognition involved self-consciousness? This question is pressing, because the thesis strikes many as obviously false.
  •  22
    The Thinking Self
    Philosophical Review 98 (1): 115. 1989.
  •  71
    The Crucial Relation in Personal Identity
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1): 131-145. 1978.
    1. What is the Problem of Personal Identity?Locke posed the problem of personal identity in one brief question, “What makes the same person?” This formulation is deceptively simple. My aim is to offer a new interpretation of the problem and to suggest a method for finding a solution.Investigations of personal identity are usually cast in terms of finding the criterion for personal identity. Yet talk of criteria is ambiguous. In one sense of the term, the criterion of personal identity would be s…Read more
  •  16
    Connecting intuitions and concepts at b 160n
    Southern Journal of Philosophy 25 (S1): 137-149. 1987.
  •  8
    On appealing to the extraordinary
    Metaphilosophy 9 (2). 1978.
  •  41
    Kant's Transcendental Psychology
    with Ralf Meerbote
    Philosophical Review 101 (4): 862. 1992.
  •  10
    Empirical Consciousness
    In Marcus Willaschek, Jürgen Stolzenberg, Georg Mohr & Stefano Bacin (eds.), Kant-Lexikon, De Gruyter. 2015.
  •  152
    Kant on self-identity
    Philosophical Review 91 (1): 41-72. 1982.
    Despite Kemp Smith's claims to the contrary, I show that there is good reason to believe that Kant was aware of Hume's attack on personal identity. My interpretive claim is that we can make sense of many of Kant's puzzling remarks in the subjective deduction by assuming that he was trying to reply to Hume's challenge. My substantive claim is that Kant succeeds in defending a notion of the self as a continuing sequence of informationally interdependent states.
  •  47
    Kant and the Mind
    Philosophical Review 104 (4): 590. 1995.
    Consciousness, self-consciousness, mental unity, and the necessary conditions for cognition are issues of paramount importance for two prima facie distinct intellectual endeavors: contemporary cognitive science and interpretations of Kant. The goal of Andrew Brook’s timely and useful book is to contribute to both of these projects by showing how a better understanding of Kant’s views can also illuminate current controversies about how to model the mind.
  •  15
    On Interpreting Kant's Thinker as Wittgenstein's 'I'
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 61 (1): 33-63. 2000.
    Although both Kant and Wittgenstein made claims about the "unknowability" of cognitive subjects, the current practice of assimilating their positions is mistaken. I argue that Allison's attempt to understand the Kantian self through the early Wittgenstein and McDowell's linking of Kant and the later Wittgenstein distort rather than illuminate. Against McDowell, I argue further that the Critique's analysis of the necessary conditions for cognition produces an account of the sources of epistemic n…Read more
  •  48
    Kant versus the Asymmetry Dogma
    Kant Yearbook 5 (1). 2013.
    One of the most widely accepted contemporary constraints on theories of self-knowledge is that they must account for the very different ways in which cognitive subjects know their own minds and the ways in which they know other minds. Through the influence of Peter Strawson, Kant is often taken to be an original source for this view. I argue that Kant is quite explicit in holding the opposite position. In a little discussed passage in the Paralogisms chapter, he argues that cognitive subjects ha…Read more
  •  84
    Book review. The logic of affect Paul Redding (review)
    Mind 110 (438): 539-542. 2001.