Christopher Peacocke

Columbia University
Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Study, University of London
  • Columbia University
    Department of Philosophy
    Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy
  • Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Study, University of London
    Other (Part-time)
University of Oxford
Faculty of Philosophy
DPhil
New York City, New York, United States of America
  •  74
    Intentionality: An Essay in the Philosophy of Mind
    Philosophical Review 95 (4): 603. 1986.
  •  20
    Consciousness and Other Minds
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 58 (1): 97-138. 1984.
  •  68
    Consciousness and Other Minds
    with Colin Mcginn
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 58 97-137. 1984.
  •  107
    Discussion of Christopher Peacocke’s A Study of Concepts (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 425. 1996.
    Christopher Peacocke’s A Study of Concepts is a dense and rewarding work. Each chapter raises many issues for discussion. I know three different people who are writing reviews of the volume. It testifies to the depth of Peacocke’s book that each reviewer is focusing on a quite different set of topics.
  •  74
    Précis of A Study of Concepts (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 407. 1996.
    The principal thesis of A Study of Concepts is that a concept is individuated by its possession condition. Concepts are here understood to be sliced as finely as epistemic possibility. So now and 6 o’clock are different concepts, even if, in context, they pick out the same time; likewise for the observational concept circular and the complex concept locus of coplanar points equidistant from a given point. In the simplest cases, a possession condition is stated by giving a true, individuating sta…Read more
  •  6
    Thoughts: An Essay on Content
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 49 (1): 178-180. 1988.
  •  119
    Computation as Involving Content: A Response to Egan
    Mind and Language 14 (2): 195-202. 1999.
    Only computational explanations of a content‐involving sort can answer certain ‘how’‐questions; can support content‐involving counterfactuals; and have the generality characteristic of psychological explanations. Purely formal characteriza‐tions of computations have none of these properties, and do not determine content. These points apply not only to psychological explanation, but to Turing machines themselves. Computational explanations which involve content are not opposed to naturalism. They…Read more
  •  182
    Interrelations: Concepts, Knowledge, Reference and Structure
    Mind and Language 19 (1): 85-98. 2004.
    This paper has five theses, which are intended to address the claims in Jerry Fodor's paper. (1) The question arises of the relation between the philosophical theory of concepts and epistemology. Neither is explanatorily prior to the other. Rather, each relies implicitly on distinctions drawn from the other. To explain what makes something knowledge, we need distinctions drawn from the theory of concepts. To explain the attitudes mentioned in a theory of concepts, we need to use the notion of kn…Read more
  •  14
    Sense and Content: Experience, Thought and Their Relations
    Philosophical Quarterly 36 (143): 278-291. 1986.
  •  44
    Christopher Peacocke, The Realm of Reason (review)
    Philosophical Review 115 (2): 243-246. 2006.
  •  14
    Being Known
    Mind 110 (440): 1105-1109. 2001.
  •  20
    New Essays on the A Priori
    Mind 111 (443): 647-652. 2002.
  •  14
    Thoughts: An Essay on Content
    Philosophy of Science 56 (2): 359-360. 1989.
  •  174
    How Are A Priori Truths Possible?1
    European Journal of Philosophy 1 (2): 175-199. 1993.
  •  17
    Theories of Concepts: A Wider Task
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 298-321. 2000.
  •  5
    Three Principles of Rationalism
    European Journal of Philosophy 10 (3): 375-397. 2002.
  •  328
    Conscious attitudes, attention, and self-knowledge
    In Crispin Wright, Barry C. Smith & Cynthia Macdonald (eds.), Knowing Our Own Minds, Oxford University Press. pp. 83. 1998.
    What is involved in the consciousness of a conscious, "occurrent" propositional attitude, such as a thought, a sudden conjecture or a conscious decision? And what is the relation of such consciousness to attention? I hope the intrinsic interest of these questions provides sufficient motivation to allow me to start by addressing them. We will not have a full understanding either of consciousness in general, nor of attention in general, until we have answers to these questions. I think there are c…Read more
  •  9
    Scenarios, concepts, and perception
    In Tim Crane (ed.), The Contents of Experience, Cambridge University Press. 1992.
  •  101
    A Reply to Bjurlöf's Objection
    Analysis 38 (3). 1978.
  •  16
    Review: Wittgenstein and Experience (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 32 (127). 1982.
  •  2
    X*—Finiteness and the Actual Language Relation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 75 (1): 147-166. 1975.
    Christopher Peacocke; X*—Finiteness and the Actual Language Relation, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Volume 75, Issue 1, 1 June 1975, Pages 147–166, h.
  •  25
    The Perception of Music: Sources of Significance: Symposium
    British Journal of Aesthetics 49 (3): 257-275. 2009.
    Representing one thing metaphorically-as something else is something that can occur in thought, imagination or perception. When a piece of music is heard as expressing some property F, some feature of the music is heard metaphorically-as F. The metaphor is exploited in the perception, rather than being represented. This account is developed and deployed to address some classical issues about music, including Wagner's point that the emotions expressed need not be those of a particular person on a…Read more
  •  51
    Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
    Philosophical Review 93 (2): 263. 1984.