Christopher Peacocke

Columbia University
Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Study, University of London
  • Columbia University
    Department of Philosophy
    Johnsonian Professor of Philosophy
  • Institute of Philosophy, School of Advanced Study, University of London
    Other (Part-time)
University of Oxford
Faculty of Philosophy
DPhil
New York City, New York, United States of America
  •  203
    Deviant Causal Chains
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 4 (1). 1979.
  • Psychological Theories of Concepts
    In A. Clark & Peter Millican (eds.), Connectionism, Concepts, and Folk Psychology, Oxford University Press. pp. 2--115. 1996.
  •  109
    Theories of concepts: A Wider task
    European Journal of Philosophy 8 (3): 298-321. 2000.
  •  81
    T n he question posed in my title is one that has been vigorously debated in philosophy for almost twenty years now. In one form or another, the idea that perceptual experience has a content that is nonconceptual is found in the writings of, among others, Jose Bermuidez, ... \n
  •  16
    Our Entitlement to Self-Knowledge
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 69 (1): 255-255. 1995.
  •  162
    Principles for possibilia
    Noûs 36 (3). 2002.
    It seems to be an obvious truth that There could be something that doesn't actually exist. That is, it seems to be obiously true that ◊∃×). It is sufficient for the truth of that there could be more people, or trees, or cars, than there actually are. It is also sufficient for the truth of that there could be some pepole, or trees, or cars that are distinct from all those that actually exist. Do and suchlike statements involve a commitment to possibilia, to things that possibly exist, but do not …Read more
  •  140
    Can possession conditions individuate concepts? (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 56 (2): 433-460. 1996.
    There are issues in the theory of concepts about which A Study of Concepts could have said more. There are also some issues about which it would have done well to say something different. The commentators in this symposium have successfully identified a series of issues of one or other of these two kinds, and I am very grateful for their thought and detailed attention. I have learned from reflection on their comments, and I take this opportunity to try to carry the discussion forward by addressi…Read more
  •  100
    The limits of intelligibility: A post-verificationist proposal
    Philosophical Review 97 (4): 463-496. 1988.
  •  51
    Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language
    Philosophical Review 93 (2): 263. 1984.
  •  39
    Phenomenology and Nonconceptual Content
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 62 (3): 609-615. 2001.
    This note aims to clarify which arguments do, and which arguments do not, tell against Conceptualism, the thesis that the representational content of experience is exclusively conceptual. Contrary to Sean Kelly's position, conceptualism has no difficulty accommodating the phenomena of color constancy and of situation‐dependence. Acknowledgment of nonconceptual content is also consistent with holding that experiences have nonrepresentational subjective features. the crucial arguments against conc…Read more
  • Can a theory of concepts explain the A Priori: A reply to Skorupski
    International Journal of Philosophical Studies 4 (1): 154-60. 1996.
  •  50
    Hacking on logic: Two comments
    Journal of Philosophy 78 (3): 168-175. 1981.
  •  245
    Objectivity
    Mind 118 (471): 739-769. 2009.
    Judgement, perception, and other mental states and events have a minimal objectivity in this sense: making the judgement or being in the mental state does not in general thereby make the judgement correct or make the perception veridical. I offer an explanation of this minimal objectivity by developing a form of constitutive transcendental argument. The argument appeals to the proper individuation of the content of judgements and perceptions. In the case of the conceptual content of judgements, …Read more
  •  103
  •  138
    The realm of reason
    Oxford University Press. 2004.
    The Realm of Reason develops a new, general theory of what it is for a thinker to be entitled to form a given belief. The theory locates entitlement in the nexus of relations between truth, content, and understanding. Peacocke formulates three principles of rationalism that articulate this conception. The principles imply that all entitlement has a component that is justificationally independent of experience. The resulting position is thus a form of rationalism, generalized to all kinds of cont…Read more
  • Understanding the past tense
    In Christoph Hoerl & Teresa McCormark (eds.), Time and Memory, Oxford University Press. 2001.
  •  3
  •  89
    Music and Experiencing Metaphorically-As: Further Delineation: Articles
    British Journal of Aesthetics 50 (2): 189-191. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  11
    Replies to Commentators
    Mind and Language 1 (4): 388-402. 1986.
  •  62
    Précis of Being Known_ _* (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 64 (3): 636-640. 2002.
    The topic of Being Known is what I call the Integration Challenge, which is the challenge of providing, for any given domain, a simultaneously acceptable metaphysics and epistemology for that domain. In virtually every domain of thought, it is a substantive task to reconcile our metaphysics and our epistemology of that domain. In some cases, we have an intuitively acceptable metaphysics, but cannot find a plausible epistemology which would allow us knowledge of truths for which that is the right…Read more
  •  75
    Christopher Peacocke presents a new theory of subjects of consciousness, together with a theory of the nature of first person representation. He identifies three sorts of self-consciousness--perspectival, reflective, and interpersonal--and argues that they are key to explaining features of our knowledge, social relations, and emotional lives