•  67
    Nisza
    Filozofia Nauki 3. 2000.
    Pojęcie niszy (otoczenia, kontekstu, siedliska, środowiska) nie cieszy się specjalnym zainteresowaniem ontologów, mimo że ma szerokie zastosowanie w rozmaitych dyscyplinach, od biologii ewolucyjnej po ekonomię. Niniejszy artykuł zawiera pierwszą teorię formalną tego pojęcia — teorię relacji pomiędzy przedmiotami a ich niszami. Teoria ta opiera się na istniejącym dorobku mereologii, topologii i teorii lokalizacji przestrzennej, które są narzędziami ontologii formalnej. Jest ona tutaj ilustrowana …Read more
  •  74
    I trabocchetti della rappresentazione spaziale
    Sistemi Intelligent 11 (1). 1999.
    This is a position article summarizing our approach to the philosophy of space and spatial representation. Our concern is mostly methodological: above all, we argue that a number of philosophical puzzles that arise in this field—puzzles concerning the nature of spatial entities, their material and mereological constitution, their relationship with the space that they occupy—stem from a confusion between semantic issues and true metaphysical concerns.
  •  78
    The methodological anarchy that characterizes much recent research in artificial intelligence and other cognitive sciences has brought into existence (sometimes resumed) a large variety of entities from a correspondingly large variety of (sometimes dubious) ontological categories. Recent work in spatial representation and reasoning is particularly indicative of this trend. Our aim in this paper is to suggest some ways of reconciling such a luxurious proliferation of entities with the sheer sobri…Read more
  •  39
    Surrounding Space
    Theory in Biosciences 121 (2): 139-162. 2002.
    The history of evolution is a history of development from less to more complex organisms. This growth in complexity of organisms goes hand in hand with a concurrent growth in complexity of environments and of organism-environment relations. It is a concern with this latter aspect of evolutionary development that motivates the present paper. We begin by outlining a theory of organism-environment relations. We then show that the theory can be applied to a range of different sorts of cases, both bi…Read more
  •  1
    True and False: An Exchange
    with Roberto Casati
    In André Chapuis & Anil Gupta (eds.), Circularity, Definition and Truth, Sole Distributor, Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers. pp. 365--370. 2000.
  •  72
    Spatial Entities
    In Oliviero Stock (ed.), Spatial and Temporal Reasoning, Kluwer Academic Publishers. 1997.
    Ordinary reasoning about space—we argue—is first and foremost reasoning about things or events located in space. Accordingly, any theory concerned with the construction of a general model of our spatial competence must be grounded on a general account of the sort of entities that may enter into the scope of the theory. Moreover, on the methodological side the emphasis on spatial entities (as opposed to purely geometrical items such as points or regions) calls for a reexamination of the conceptua…Read more
  •  47
    Sfondo e figura
    Rivista di Estetica 43 (24): 38-40. 2003.
    A dialogue between a figure and its background, illustrating that the perceptual conditions that determine which is which are not as clear as standard Gestalt theory dictates.
  •  74
    All the Things You Are
    In Gabriele Usberti (ed.), Modi dell’oggettività, Bompiani. 2000.
    An imaginary dialogue between Andrea Bonomi and Gonzalo Pirobutirro (the main character of Gadda’s novel La cognizione del dolore) aiming to challenge Bonomi’s tenet that a work of fiction defines a domain of objects which is closed with respect to the actual world.
  •  52
    Esercizi di attenzione
    Riga 24. 2005.
    A brief study of Saul Steinberg’s works on shadows and reflections, and of the seemingly paradoxical world that emerges from such works.
  •  51
    True and False: An Exchange
    In André Chapuis & Anil Gupta (eds.), Circularity, Definition and Truth, Sole Distributor, Munshiram Manoharlal Publishers. pp. 365-370. 2000.
    Classically, truth and falsehood are opposite, and so are logical truth and logical falsehood. In this paper we imagine a situation in which the opposition is so pervasive in the language we use as to threaten the very possibility of telling truth from falsehood. The example exploits a suggestion of Ramsey’s to the effect that negation can be expressed simply by writing the negated sentence upside down. The difference between ‘p’ and ‘~~p’ disappears, the principle of double negation becomes tri…Read more
  •  103
    Unsharpenable Vagueness
    Philosophical Topics 28 (1): 1-10. 2000.
    A plausible thought about vagueness is that it involves semantic incompleteness. To say that a predicate is vague is to say (at the very least) that its extension is incompletely specified. Where there is incomplete specification of extension there is indeterminacy, an indeterminacy between various ways in which the specification of the predicate might be completed or sharpened. In this paper we show that this idea is bound to founder by presenting an argument to the effect that there are vague …Read more
  • Landscapes in Logic (Volume on Philosophical Logics) (edited book)
    College Publications. forthcoming.
  •  127
    Event Location and Vagueness
    Philosophical Studies 128 (2): 313-336. 2006.
    Most event-referring expressions are vague; it is utterly difficult, if not impossible, to specify the exact spatiotemporal location of an event from the words that we use to refer to it. We argue that in spite of certain prima facie obstacles, such vagueness can be given a purely semantic (broadly supervaluational) account
  •  56
    Sur la frontière entre ontologie matérielle et ontologie formelle
    RÉPHA, revue étudiante de philosophie analytique 3 53-61. 2011.
  • Logica, Seconda edizione
    with John Nolt and Dennis A. Rohatyn
    McGraw-Hill Italia. 2007.
    Extended revised edition of "Logica" (2003)
  •  22
    Logica
    with John Nolt and Dennis A. Rohatyn
    McGraw-Hill Italia. 2003.
    Italian translation of "Schaum's Outline of Theory and Problems of Logic" (1988)
  •  14
    Complementary Proof Nets for Classical Logic
    Logica Universalis 17 (4): 411-432. 2023.
    A complementary system for a given logic is a proof system whose theorems are exactly the formulas that are not valid according to the logic in question. This article is a contribution to the complementary proof theory of classical propositional logic. In particular, we present a complementary proof-net system, $$\textsf{CPN}$$ CPN, that is sound and complete with respect to the set of all classically invalid (one-side) sequents. We also show that cut elimination in $$\textsf{CPN}$$ CPN enjoys s…Read more
  •  16
    Thinking about space is thinking about spatial things. The table is on the carpet; hence the carpet is under the table. The vase is in the box; hence the box is not in the vase. But what does it mean for an object to be somewhere? How are objects tied to the space they occupy? This book is concerned with these and other fundamental issues in the philosophy of spatial representation. Our starting point is an analysis of the interplay between mereology (the study of part/whole relations), topology…Read more
  •  6
    Undetached Parts and Disconnected Wholes
    In Christer Svennerlind, Almäng Jan & Rögnvaldur Ingthorsson (eds.), Johanssonian Investigations: Essays in Honour of Ingvar Johansson on His Seventieth Birthday, Ontos Verlag. pp. 696-708. 2013.
  •  60
    Mereology then and now
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 24 (4). 2015.
    This paper offers a critical reconstruction of the motivations that led to the development of mereology as we know it today, along with a brief description of some problems that define current research in the field.
  •  34
    The purpose of Parts and Places, say Casati and Varzi in their introduction, is to construct “a theory of our spatial competence,” a theory that will lay bare how we conceive of space and the things that lie within it. Its purpose, then, is psychological, not metaphysical. Its object of study is not space. It is not the things that lie within it. Rather its object of study is us. In this regard, Parts and Places is at best a mixed success.
  •  104
    A philosophical dialogue on the functioning, the limits, and the paradoxes of our electoral practices, dealing with such basic questions as: What is a vote? How do we count votes? And do votes really count?
  •  69
    Topological Essentialism
    Philosophical Studies 100 (3): 217-236. 2000.
    Considering topology as an extension of mereology, this paper analyses topological variants of mereological essentialism (the thesis that an object could not have different parts than the ones it has). In particular, we examine de dicto and de re versions of two theses: (i) that an object cannot change its external connections (e.g., adjacent objects cannot be separated), and (ii) that an object cannot change its topological genus (e.g., a doughnut cannot turn into a sphere). Stronger forms of s…Read more
  •  20
    Holes are a good example of the sort of entity that down-to-earth philosophers would be inclined to expel from their ontological inventory. In this work we argue instead in favor of their existence and explore the consequences of this liberality—odd as they might appear. We examine the ontology of holes, their geometry, their part-whole relations, their identity and their causal role, the ways we perceive them. We distinguish three basic kinds of holes: blind hollows, perforating tunnels, and in…Read more
  •  74
    Foreword to ''Lesser Kinds''
    The Monist 90 (3): 331-332. 2007.
    This issue of The Monist is devoted to the metaphysics of lesser kinds, which is to say those kinds of entity that are not generally recognized as occupying a prominent position in the categorial structure of the world. Why bother? We offer two sorts of reason. The first is methodological. In mathematics, it is common practice to study certain functions (for instance) by considering limit cases: What if x = 0? What if x is larger than any assigned value? Physics, too, often studies the (idealize…Read more
  •  16
    Ontological commitment and reconstructivism
    Erkenntnis 55 (1): 33-50. 2001.
    Some forms of analytic reconstructivism take natural language (and common sense at large) to be ontologically opaque: ordinary sentences must be suitably rewritten or paraphrased before questions of ontological commitment may be raised. Other forms of reconstructivism take the commitment of ordinary language at face value, but regard it as metaphysically misleading: common-sense objects exist, but they are not what we normally think they are. This paper is an attempt to clarify and critically as…Read more
  •  1
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Rainer Bäuerle, N. C. A. Da Costa, O. Bueno, Javier De Lorenzo, Alberto Zanardo, Alan R. Perreiah, K. Misiuna, H. Sinaceur, T. Hailperin, S. Bringsjord, T. Wiliamson, and Barry Smith
    History and Philosophy of Logic 17 (1-2): 155-177. 1996.
    Gennaro Chtjerchia, Dynamics of meaning: anaphora, presupposition, and the the of grammar. Chicago and London: The University of Chicago Press, 1995.xv+ 270 pp, £59.95, £31.95 G. Pr...
  •  45
    Intuitionistic Mereology II: Overlap and Disjointness
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 52 (4): 1197-1233. 2023.
    This paper extends the axiomatic treatment of intuitionistic mereology introduced in Maffezioli and Varzi (_Synthese, 198_(S18), 4277–4302 2021 ) by examining the behavior of constructive notions of overlap and disjointness. We consider both (i) various ways of defining such notions in terms of other intuitionistic mereological primitives, and (ii) the possibility of treating them as mereological primitives of their own.
  •  60
    On Three Axiom Systems for Classical Mereology
    Logic and Logical Philosophy 28 (2). 2019.
    Paul Hovda’s excellent paper ‘What Is Classical Mereology?' has fruitfully reshaped the debate concerning the axiomatic foundations of classical mereology. Precisely because of the importance of Hovda’s work and its usefulness as a reference tool, we note here that one of the five axiom systems presented therein, corresponding the ‘Third Way’ to classical mereology, is defective and must be amended. In addition, we note that two other axiom systems, corresponding to the ‘First Way’ and to the ‘F…Read more