•  141
    Deontology
    In David Copp (ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  156
    Unprincipled Ethics
    In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral particularism, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  •  94
    Mapping moral motivation
    with Eve Garrard
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 1 (1): 45-59. 1998.
    In this paper we defend a version of moral internalism and a cognitivist account of motivation against recent criticisms. The internalist thesis we espouse claims that, if an agent believes she has reason to A, then she is motivated to A. Discussion of counter-examples has been clouded by the absence of a clear account of the nature of motivation. While we can only begin to provide such an account in this paper, we do enough to show that our version of internalism can be defended against putativ…Read more
  •  52
  •  5
    Moral Dilemmas
    Philosophical Books 30 (4): 244-247. 1989.
  •  143
    Conditional and Conditioned Reasons
    Utilitas 14 (2): 240. 2002.
    This paper is a brief reponse to some of Douglas Portmore's criticisms of our version of the agent-relative/agent-neutral distinction
  •  365
    From Darkness into Light? Reflections on Wandering in Darkness
    European Journal for Philosophy of Religion 4 (3): 123--135. 2012.
  •  116
    Contours of the Practical
    In David Bakhurst, Margaret Olivia Little & Brad Hooker (eds.), Thinking about reasons: themes from the philosophy of Jonathan Dancy, Oxford University Press. pp. 240. 2013.
  •  44
    A Distinctively Moral Scepticism?
    Philosophical Books 49 (3): 207-217. 2008.
    No Abstract
  •  22
    Response to Diamond
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 29 85-86. 1991.
    Where two people differ about the application of some term to a particular object, to what can they appeal to settle their disagreement? In my paper I suggested that the disputants can legitimately draw attention to various features of the contested case to try to show the continuity, or lack of it, between this case and other instances that fall under the concept. In so doing they are offering reasons to justify their judgement in this particular case
  •  44
    I—David McNaughton and Piers Rawling: Descriptivism, Normativity and the Metaphysics of Reasons
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 77 (1): 23-45. 2003.
    Simon Blackburn can be seen as challenging those committed to sui generis moral facts to explain the supervenience of the moral on the descriptive. We hold that normative facts in general are sui generis. We also hold that the normative supervenes on the descriptive, and we here endeavour to answer the generalization of Blackburn's challenge. In the course of pursuing this answer, we suggest that Frank Jackson's descriptivism rests on a conception of properties inappropriate to discussions of no…Read more
  •  153
    Some of the virtues have a very stable place in our understanding of goodness – beneficence and courage are unlikely ever to lose their high standing. But other virtues have something like a life cycle: they move from a marginal status to to a central one, and sometimes they move back again to the margins, or even beyond the domain of virtue altogether. Chastity is one example of this; humility is another. There was a period in which humility wasn’t a virtue at all (see Aristotle on the great-so…Read more
  •  114
    Deontology and value
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 47 197-208. 2000.
    Integration and coherence are central values in human existence. It would be a serious objection to any proposed way of life that it led to us being alienated or cut off from others or from some importan part of ourselves. Morality, with the strenuous demands it makes on us, is one area in which alienation is both particularly threatening and peculiarly undesirable. If morality cuts us off from some important part of ourselves then it appears unattractive, and if it cuts us off from others then …Read more
  •  40
    Butler's ethics
    In Roger Crisp (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of the History of Ethics, Oxford University Press. 2013.
    This chapter analyses Butler's ethical theories, which are found primarily in Fifteen Sermons and A Dissertation of the Nature of Virtue. It covers his notions of superiority and authority, the supremacy of conscience, virtue, benevolence, and self-love.
  •  63
    Speak No Evil?1
    with Eve Garrard
    Midwest Studies in Philosophy 36 (1): 1-17. 2012.
  •  1
    Practical Inferences
    Philosophical Books 28 (1): 42-44. 1987.
  •  112
    Honoring and promoting values
    Ethics 102 (4): 835-843. 1992.
  •  225
    Scanlon suggests a buck-passing account of goodness. To say that something is good is not to give a reason to, say, favour it; rather it is to say that there are such reasons. When it comes to wrongness, however, Scanlon rejects a buck-passing account: to say that j ing is wrong is, on his view, to give a sufficient moral reason not to j. Philip Stratton-Lake 2003 argues that Scanlon can evade a redundancy objection against his (Scanlon’s) view of wrongness by adopting a buck-passing account of …Read more
  •  228
    An unconnected Heap of duties?
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185): 433-447. 1996.
  •  261
    The making/evidential reason distinction
    with P. Rawling
    Analysis 71 (1): 100-102. 2011.
    Stephen Kearns and Daniel Star have made the following interesting proposal concerning the relation between practical reasons and evidence : Necessarily: A fact F is a reason for you to φ iff F is evidence that you ought to φ We're not sure about this. Although moving from left to right might be OK, the converse is problematic. For example, the fact that your reliable friend told you that you have overriding moral reason to φ is …
  •  458
    In defence of unconditional forgiveness
    with Eve Garrard
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (1). 2003.
    In this paper, the principal objections to unconditional forgiveness are canvassed, primarily that it fails to take wrongdoing seriously enough, and that it displays a lack of self-respect. It is argued that these objections stem from a mistaken understanding of what forgiveness actually involves, including the erroneous view that forgiveness involves some degree of condoning of the offence, and is incompatible with blaming the offender or punishing him. Two positive reasons for endorsing uncond…Read more
  •  28
    Duty, rationality, and practical reasons
    In Piers Rawling & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 110--131. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling present a view on which practical reasons are facts, such as the fact that the rubbish bin is full. This is a non-normative fact, but it is a reason for you to do something, namely take the rubbish out. They see rationality as a matter of consistency. And they see duty as neither purely a matter of rationality nor of practical reason: on the one hand, the rational sociopath is immoral; but, on the other, morality does not require that we always act on the weightiest moral …Read more
  •  82
    Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1): 354-374. 2009.
    We reject Moorean holism about value—the view that the value of the whole does not equal the sum of the values of its parts. We propose an alternative aggregative holism according to which the value of a state of affairs is the sum of the values of its constituent states. But these constituents must be evaluated in situ
  •  34
    Thick Concepts Revisited: A Reply to Burton
    with Eve Garrard
    Analysis 53 (1). 1993.