•  112
    Honoring and promoting values
    Ethics 102 (4): 835-843. 1992.
  •  225
    Scanlon suggests a buck-passing account of goodness. To say that something is good is not to give a reason to, say, favour it; rather it is to say that there are such reasons. When it comes to wrongness, however, Scanlon rejects a buck-passing account: to say that j ing is wrong is, on his view, to give a sufficient moral reason not to j. Philip Stratton-Lake 2003 argues that Scanlon can evade a redundancy objection against his (Scanlon’s) view of wrongness by adopting a buck-passing account of …Read more
  •  228
    An unconnected Heap of duties?
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (185): 433-447. 1996.
  •  261
    The making/evidential reason distinction
    with P. Rawling
    Analysis 71 (1): 100-102. 2011.
    Stephen Kearns and Daniel Star have made the following interesting proposal concerning the relation between practical reasons and evidence : Necessarily: A fact F is a reason for you to φ iff F is evidence that you ought to φ We're not sure about this. Although moving from left to right might be OK, the converse is problematic. For example, the fact that your reliable friend told you that you have overriding moral reason to φ is …
  •  458
    In defence of unconditional forgiveness
    with Eve Garrard
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 103 (1). 2003.
    In this paper, the principal objections to unconditional forgiveness are canvassed, primarily that it fails to take wrongdoing seriously enough, and that it displays a lack of self-respect. It is argued that these objections stem from a mistaken understanding of what forgiveness actually involves, including the erroneous view that forgiveness involves some degree of condoning of the offence, and is incompatible with blaming the offender or punishing him. Two positive reasons for endorsing uncond…Read more
  •  28
    Duty, rationality, and practical reasons
    In Piers Rawling & Alfred R. Mele (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 110--131. 2004.
    McNaughton and Rawling present a view on which practical reasons are facts, such as the fact that the rubbish bin is full. This is a non-normative fact, but it is a reason for you to do something, namely take the rubbish out. They see rationality as a matter of consistency. And they see duty as neither purely a matter of rationality nor of practical reason: on the one hand, the rational sociopath is immoral; but, on the other, morality does not require that we always act on the weightiest moral …Read more
  •  82
    Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1): 354-374. 2009.
    We reject Moorean holism about value—the view that the value of the whole does not equal the sum of the values of its parts. We propose an alternative aggregative holism according to which the value of a state of affairs is the sum of the values of its constituent states. But these constituents must be evaluated in situ
  •  34
    Thick Concepts Revisited: A Reply to Burton
    with Eve Garrard
    Analysis 53 (1). 1993.
  •  53
    Reparation and Atonement
    Religious Studies 28 (2). 1992.
    Richard Swinburne (in his "Responsibility and Atonement") argues for a sacrificial version of the Atonement, in which the individual penitent offers the life of Christ to God in (partial) reparation for his sins. I argue that any version of this account is both conceptually incoherent and morally unsatisfying and offer in its place a version of the exemplary theory of the Atonement which, I claim, meets the conditions he lays down for any satisfactory account
  •  602
    This book introduces the reader to ethics by examining a current and important debate. During the last fifty years the orthodox position in ethics has been a broadly non-cognitivist one: since there are no moral facts, moral remarks are best understood, not as attempting to describe the world, but as having some other function - such as expressing the attitudes or preferences of the speaker. In recent years this position has been increasingly challenged by moral realists who maintain that there …Read more
  •  211
    Value and Agent-Relative Reasons
    Utilitas 7 (1): 31. 1995.
    In recent years the distinction between agent-relative and agent-neutral reasons has been taken by many to play a key role in distinguishing deontology from consequentialism. It is central to all universalist consequentialist theories that value is determined impersonally; the real value of any state of affairs does not depend on the point of view of the agent. No reference, therefore, to the agent or to his or her position in the world need enter into a consequentialist understanding of what ma…Read more
  • Intuitionism
    In Hugh LaFollette - (ed.), The Blackwell Guide to Ethical Theory, Blackwell. pp. 268--87. 2000.
  •  274
    significant role for accomplishment thereby admits a ‘Trojan Horse’ (267).1 To abandon hedonism in favour of a conception of well-being that incorporates achievement is to take the first step down a slippery slope toward the collapse of the other two pillars of utilitarian morality: welfarism and consequentialism. We shall argue that Crisp’s arguments do not support these conclusions. We begin with welfarism. Crisp defines it thus: ‘Well-being is the only value. Everything good must be good for …Read more
  •  2
    The problem of evil: A deontological perspective
    In Richard Swinburne & Alan G. Padgett (eds.), Reason and the Christian Religion: Essays in Honour of Richard Swinburne, Oxford University Press. pp. 329--351. 1994.
  •  94
    Forgiving for good
    with Eve Garrard
    The Philosophers' Magazine 52 (52): 43-48. 2011.
    The repentant offender has placed himself on the side of right, so to speak – he now stands with the victim against his own previous bad behaviour, which he now rejects. He’s a proper recipient for the gift of forgiveness. It can be morally appropriate to wipe the slate clean for him. But the unrepentant offender has undergone no such change. Why should we wipe the slate clean for such a person?
  •  497
    On defending deontology
    Ratio 11 (1). 1998.
    This paper comprises three sections. First, we offer a traditional defence of deontology, in the manner of, for example, W.D. Ross (1965). The leading idea of such a defence is that the right is independent of the good. Second, we modify the now standard account of the distinction, in terms of the agent-relative/agentneutral divide, between deontology and consequentialism. (This modification is necessary if indirect consequentialism is to count as a form of consequentialism.) Third, we challenge…Read more
  •  20
    Morality and Universality: Essays on Ethical Universalizability
    Philosophical Books 28 (2): 99-102. 1987.
  • Forgiveness and forgivingness
    with Eve Garrard
    In S. van Hooft, N. Athanassoulis, J. Kawall, J. Oakley & L. van Zyl (eds.), The handbook of virtue ethics, Acumen Publishing. 2014.
  •  132
  •  62
    Review of Michael Huemer, Ethical Intuitionism (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2006 (9). 2006.
  • Moral Vision: An Introduction to Ethics
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 30 (3): 188-189. 1988.
  •  5
  •  69