•  21
    Surrounding Free Will: Philosophy, Psychology, Neuroscience (edited book)
    Oxford University Press USA. 2014.
    This volume showcases cutting-edge scholarship from The Big Questions in Free Will project, funded by a grant from the John Templeton Foundation and directed by Alfred R. Mele. It explores the subject of free will from the perspectives of neuroscience; social, cognitive, and developmental psychology; and philosophy. The volume consists of fourteen new articles and an introduction from top-ranked contributors, all of whom bring fresh perspectives to the question of free will. They investigate que…Read more
  •  32
    Free Will and Luck
    Oxford University Press USA. 2006.
    Mele's ultimate purpose in this book is to help readers think more clearly about free will. He identifies and makes vivid the most important conceptual obstacles to justified belief in the existence of free will and meets them head on. Mele clarifies the central issue in the philosophical debate about free will and moral responsibility, criticizes various influential contemporary theories about free will, and develops two overlapping conceptions of free will - one for readers who are convinced t…Read more
  •  1
    Aristotle's Theory of Human Motivation
    Dissertation, University of Michigan. 1979.
  •  1
  • D.N. Walton, "Courage: A philosophical investigation"
    International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 23 (2): 117. 1988.
  •  15
    The Significance of Free Will (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 95 (11): 581-584. 1998.
    A book review of Robert Kane's The Significance of Free Will.
  •  78
    Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 81 (2): 292-295. 2003.
    Book Information Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from Harry Frankfurt. Edited by Sarah Buss and Lee Overton. MIT Press. Cambridge MA. 2002. Pp. 381.
  •  101
    Review: Living Without Free Will (review)
    Mind 112 (446): 375-378. 2003.
  •  15
    Free Will and Consciousness: How Might They Work? (New York: OUP, 2010) (edited book)
    with Kathleen Vohs and Roy Baumeister
    Oxford University Press. 2010.
    This volume is aimed at readers who wish to move beyond debates about the existence of free will and the efficacy of consciousness and closer to appreciating how free will and consciousness might operate. It draws from philosophy and psychology, the two fields that have grappled most fundamentally with these issues. In this wide-ranging volume, the contributors explore such issues as how free will is connected to rational choice, planning, and self-control; roles for consciousness in decision ma…Read more
  •  55
    Desiring to Try: Reply to Adams
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 24 (4). 1994.
    Frederick Adams has tried again to object to my argument in "He Wants to Try"; his new attempt includes both an account of the constitution of trying and a corresponding account of desiring to try. My aim here is to show that his new efforts fail to undermine T and to develop some related problems for his positive view.
  •  78
    Reasonology and False Beliefs
    Philosophical Papers 36 (1): 91-118. 2007.
    Whereas some philosophers view all reasons for action as psychological states of agents, others—objective favourers theorists—locate the overwhelming majority of reasons for action outside the agent, in items that objectively favour courses of action. (The latter may count such psychological states as a person's belief that demons dance in his kitchen as a reason for him to seek psychiatric help.) This article explores options that objective favourers theorists have regarding cases in which, owi…Read more
  •  25
    Aristotle on the Proximate Efficient Cause of Action
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 14 (sup1): 133-155. 1984.
    In this paper I shall attempt to locate and articulate Aristotle's answer to a foundational question in the theory of action - viz., 'what is the proximate (efficient) cause of action?' This task is certainly of historical importance, since one cannot hope to understand Aristotle's interesting and influential theory of action without understanding his views on the proximate efficient cause of action. But the present project is not, I should think, of historical interest alone; for it has recentl…Read more
  •  116
    The folk concept of intentional action: A commentary
    Journal of Cognition and Culture 6 (1-2): 277-290. 2006.
    In this commentary, I discuss the three main articles in this volume that present survey data relevant to a search for something that might merit the label “the folk concept of intentional action” – the articles by Joshua Knobe and Arudra Burra, Bertram Malle, and Thomas Nadelhoffer. My guiding question is this: What shape might we find in an analysis of intentional action that takes at face value the results of all of the relevant surveys about vignettes discussed in these three articles?1 To s…Read more
  •  21
    Motivated Belief
    Behavior and Philosophy 21 (2). 1993.
    In this essay, I focus on Ainslie's interesting and bold view of belief and on its implications for akratic belief.
  •  277
    Manipulation, Moral Responsibility, and Bullet Biting
    The Journal of Ethics 17 (3): 167-184. 2013.
    This article’s guiding question is about bullet biting: When should compatibilists about moral responsibility bite the bullet in responding to stories used in arguments for incompatibilism about moral responsibility? Featured stories are vignettes in which agents’ systems of values are radically reversed by means of brainwashing and the story behind the zygote argument. The malady known as “intuition deficit disorder” is also discussed.
  •  132
    Direct control
    Philosophical Studies 174 (2): 275-290. 2017.
    This article’s aim is to shed light on direct control, especially as it pertains to free will. I sketch two ways of conceiving of such control. Both sketches extend to decision making. Issues addressed include the problem of present luck and the relationship between direct control and complete control.
  •  967
    Self-Deception and Delusions
    European Journal of Analytic Philosophy 2 (1): 109-124. 2006.
    My central question in this paper is how delusional beliefs are related to self-deception. In section 1, I summarize my position on what self-deception is and how representative instances of it are to be explained. I turn to delusions in section 2, where I focus on the Capgras delusion, delusional jealousy (or the Othello syndrome), and the reverse Othello syndrome.
  •  101
    History and Personal Autonomy
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 23 (2). 1993.
    John Christman, in 'Autonomy and Personal History,' advances a novel genetic or historical account of individual autonomy.1 He formulates 'the conditions of the [i.e., his] new model of autonomy' as follows: (i) A person Pis autonomous relative to some desireD if it is the case that P did not resist the development of D when attending to this process of development, or P would not have resisted that development had P attended to the process; (ii) The lack of resistance to the development of D di…Read more
  •  110
    Acting Intentionally: Probing Folk Notions.
    In Bertram Malle, L. J. Moses & Dare Baldwin (eds.), Intentions and Intentionality: Foundations of Social Cognition, Mit Press. pp. 27--43. 2001.
    In the first section, I will argue that the folk concept of necessary conditions for intentional action needs refinement. In the second and third sections, I will identify some additional issues one would need to explore in con- structing a statement of individually necessary and jointly sufficient conditions for intentional action. I will conclude with a brief discussion of the conceptual analyst’s task.
  •  24
    Soft Libertarianism and Frankfurt-Style Scenarios
    Philosophical Topics 24 (2): 123-141. 1996.
    Traditional libertarians about freedom of choice and action and about moral responsibility are hard-line incompatibilists. They claim that these freedoms (which they believe to be possessed by at least some human beings) are incompatible with determinism, and they take the same view of moral responsibility. I call them hard libertarians. A softer line is available to theorists who have libertarian sympathies. A theorist may leave it open that freedom of choice and action and moral responsibil…Read more
  •  12
    Living Without Free Will (review)
    Mind 112 (446): 375-378. 2003.
  •  17
    Intending and the Balance of Motivation
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 65 (4): 370-376. 1984.
    How is what we intend to do related to what we are most motivated to do? I shall argue that the relationship in question is more complex than is often thought and that the source of complexity, at least at one level of analysis, lies in two things: a role which evaluation often plays in the formation or acquisition of intentions, and an occasional lack of alignment between an agent's evaluations of his reasons for action and the motivation force of those reasons.
  •  79
    Persisting intentions
    Noûs 41 (4). 2007.
    Al is nearly finished sweeping his kitchen floor when he notices, on a counter, a corkscrew that should be put in a drawer. He intends to put the corkscrew away as soon as he is finished with the floor; but by the time he returns the broom and dustpan to the closet, he has forgotten what he intended to do. Al knows (or has a true belief) that there is something he intended to do now in the kitchen. He gazes around the room and tries to recall what it was. Within a minute or so, without seeing th…Read more
  •  112
    This chapter defends the thesis that Benjamin Libet’s data do not justify his claim that “the brain ‘decides’ to initiate or, at least, to prepare to initiate [certain actions] before there is any reportable subjective awareness that such a decision has taken place” and do not justify associated worries about free will. The data are examined in light of familiar distinctions in action theory: for example, the distinction between deciding and wanting and the distinction between intending and want…Read more