•  44
    Manipulated Agents: Replies to Fischer, Haji, and McKenna
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (2): 299-309. 2021.
    This article is part of a symposium on Alfred Mele’s Manipulated Agents: A Window to Moral Responsibility. It is Mele’s response to John Fischer, Ishtiyaque Haji, and Michael McKenna. Topics discussed include the bearing of manipulation on moral responsibility, the zygote argument, the importance of scenarios in which manipulators radically reverse an agent’s values, positive versus negative historical requirements for moral responsibility, the scope of moral responsibility, the value of intuiti…Read more
  •  31
    Manipulated Agents: Précis
    Criminal Law and Philosophy 15 (2): 249-253. 2020.
    This précis kicks off an invited symposium on Alfred R. Mele.
  •  1114
    Intentional Action Without Knowledge
    Synthese 197 1-13. 2020.
    In order to be doing something intentionally, must one know that one is doing it? Some philosophers have answered yes. Our aim is to test a version of this knowledge thesis, what we call the Knowledge/Awareness Thesis, or KAT. KAT states that an agent is doing something intentionally only if he knows that he is doing it or is aware that he is doing it. Here, using vignettes featuring skilled action and vignettes featuring habitual action, we provide evidence that, in various scenarios, a majori…Read more
  •  88
    Free Will and Luck: Compatibilism versus Incompatibilism
    The Monist 103 (3): 262-277. 2020.
    Compatibilists about free will maintain that free will is compatible with determinism, and incompatibilists disagree. Incompatibilist believers in free will have been challenged to solve a problem that luck poses for them—the problem of present luck. This article articulates that challenge and then explores a novel compatibilist view recently proposed by Christian List. It is argued that List’s view, unlike standard compatibilist views, faces a very similar problem about luck.
  •  88
    Direct Versus Indirect: Control, Moral Responsibility, and Free Action
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 102 (3): 559-573. 2020.
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, EarlyView.
  •  13
    Surrounding Self-Control (edited book)
    Oxford University Press, Usa. 2020.
    Self-control has gained enormous attention in recent years both in philosophy and the mind sciences, for it has profound implications on so many aspects of human life. Overcoming temptation, improving cognitive functioning, making life-altering decisions, and numerous other challenges all depend upon self-control. But recent developments in the philosophy of mind and in action theory, as well as in psychology, are now testing some of the assumptions about the nature of self-control previously he…Read more
  •  33
    Weakness of Will and Davidson’s Paradox of Irrationality: A Response to Zheng
    Dao: A Journal of Comparative Philosophy 18 (4): 597-602. 2019.
  •  65
    Moral responsibility and manipulation: on a novel argument against historicism
    Philosophical Studies 177 (10): 3143-3154. 2020.
    Taylor Cyr offers a novel argument against, as he puts it, “all versions of historicism” about direct moral responsibility. The argument features constitutive luck and a comparison of manipulated agents and young agents performing the first actions for which they are morally responsible. Here it is argued that Cyr’s argument misses its mark. Alfred Mele’s historicism is highlighted.
  •  178
    The Role of Intention in Intentional Action
    with Frederick Adams
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 19 (4). 1989.
    A great deal of attention has been paid in recent years to the function- al roles of intentions in intentional action. In this paper we sketch and defend a position on this issue while attacking a provocative alternative. Our position has its roots in a cybernetic theory of purposive behavior and is only part of the larger task of understanding all goal-directed behavior. Indeed, a unified model of goal-directed behavior, with appropriate modifications for different types of systems, is a long-r…Read more
  •  233
    The Intention/Volition Debate
    with Frederick Adams
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 22 (3): 323-337. 1992.
    People intend to do things, try to do things, and do things. Do they also will to do things? More precisely, if people will to do things and their willing bears upon what they do, is willing, or volition, something distinct from intending and trying? This question is central to the intention/volition debate, a debate about the ingredients of the best theory of the nature and explanation of human action. A variety of competing conceptions of volition, intention, and trying have been advanced in t…Read more
  •  11
    Free will and luck: Précis
    Philosophical Explorations 10 (2): 153-155. 2007.
    I believe that human beings sometimes act freely and are morally responsible for some of what they do. If free will is the power to act freely, then I believe in free will. In Free Will and Luck, I try to make salient the most difficult conceptual problems that my belief encounters, and I develop solutions to those problems. I also expose some pseudo-problems along the way.
  •  47
    In Manipulated Agents, Alfred R. Mele examines the role one's history plays in whether or not one is morally responsible for one's actions. Mele develops a "history-sensitive" theory of moral responsibility through reflection on a wide range of thought experiments which feature agents who have been manipulated or designed in ways that directly affect their actions.
  •  3
    Liberation from Self: A Theory of Personal Autonomy (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 58 (4): 995-996. 1998.
    A book review of Bernard Berofksy's Liberation from Self: A Theory of Personal Autonomy.
  •  170
    Fischer and Ravizza on Moral Responsibility
    The Journal of Ethics 10 (3): 283-294. 2006.
    The author argued elsewhere that a necessary condition that John Fischer and Mark Ravizza offer for moral responsibility is too strong and that the sufficient conditions they offer are too weak. This article is a critical examination of their reply. Topics discussed include blameworthiness, irresistible desires, moral responsibility, reactive attitudes, and reasons responsiveness
  •  8
    Although much human action serves as proof that irrational behavior is remarkably common, certain forms of irrationality--most notably, incontinent action and self-deception--pose such difficult theoretical problems that philosophers have rejected them as logically or psychologically impossible. Here, Mele shows that, and how, incontinent action and self-deception are indeed possible. Drawing upon recent experimental work in the psychology of action and inference, he advances naturalized explana…Read more
  •  73
    Free Will, Moral Responsibility, and Scientific Epiphenomenalism
    Frontiers in Psychology 9 426871. 2018.
    This article addresses two influential lines of argument for what might be termed “scientific epiphenomenalism” about conscious intentions – the thesis that neither conscious intentions nor their physical correlates are among the causes of bodily motions – and links this thesis to skepticism about free will and moral responsibility. One line of argument is based on Benjamin Libet’s neuroscientific work on free will. The other is based on a mixed bag of findings presented by social psychologist D…Read more
  •  45
    Is Free Will Dead (Again)?
    The Philosophers' Magazine 83 80-86. 2018.
    The death of free will has been announced many times. Often neuroscientists get the credit for killing it. Over the past fifteen years or so, I have devoted a lot of time and energy to explaining why the news is premature at best. Despite my efforts, the obituaries continue to emerge. Here I will content myself with tracing an interesting strand in the ongoing debate about whether neuroscientists have killed free will and commenting on a recent development that takes us beyond neuroscience to so…Read more
  •  76
    On snubbing proximal intentions
    Philosophical Studies 176 (11): 2833-2853. 2019.
    In the simplest case, a proximal intention is an intention one has now to do something now. Recently, some philosophers have argued that proximal intentions do much less work than they are sometimes regarded as doing. This article rebuts these arguments, explains why the concept of proximal intentions is important for some scientific work on intentional action, and sketches an empirical approach to identifying proximal intentions. Ordinary usage of “intend” and the place of intention in folk psy…Read more
  •  15
    When Are We Self-Deceived?
    Humana Mente 5 (20). 2012.
    This article’s point of departure is a proto-analysis that I have suggested of entering self-deception in acquiring a belief and an associated set of jointly sufficient conditions for self-deception that I have proposed. Partly with the aim of fleshing out an important member of the proposed set of conditions, I provide a sketch of my view about how self-deception happens. I then return to the proposed set of jointly sufficient conditions and offer a pair of amendments.
  •  14
    Aristotle's Philosophy of Action (review)
    Noûs 20 (4): 562-565. 1986.
  •  481
    Autonomous Agents: From Self Control to Autonomy
    Oxford University Press. 1995.
    Autonomous Agents addresses the related topics of self-control and individual autonomy. "Self-control" is defined as the opposite of akrasia-weakness of will. The study of self-control seeks to understand the concept of its own terms, followed by an examination of its bearing on one's actions, beliefs, emotions, and personal values. It goes on to consider how a proper understanding of self-control and its manifestations can shed light on personal autonomy and autonomous behaviour. Perspicuous, o…Read more
  •  30
    A book review of Jonathan Adler's Belief's Own Ethics.
  •  57
    Ordinary people think free will is a lack of constraint, not the presence of a soul
    with Andrew J. Vonasch and Roy F. Baumeister
    Consciousness and Cognition 60 133-151. 2018.
    Four experiments supported the hypothesis that ordinary people understand free will as meaning unconstrained choice, not having a soul. People consistently rated free will as being high unless reduced by internal constraints (i.e., things that impaired people’s mental abilities to make choices) or external constraints (i.e., situations that hampered people’s abilities to choose and act as they desired). Scientific paradigms that have been argued to disprove free will were seen as reducing, but u…Read more
  •  62
    Diana and Ernie return: on Carolina Sartorio’s Causation and Free Will
    Philosophical Studies 175 (6): 1525-1533. 2018.
    In the final chapter of her Causation and Free Will, Carolina Sartorio offers a novel reply to an original-design argument for the thesis that determinism is incompatible with free will and moral responsibility, an argument that resembles Alfred Mele’s zygote argument in Free Will and Luck. This article assesses the merits of her reply. It is concluded that Sartorio has more work to do if she is to lay this style of argument to rest.
  •  63
    Mele develops a view of paradigmatically free actions--including decisions--as indeterministically caused by their proximal causes. He mounts a masterful defense of this thesis that includes solutions to problems about luck and control widely discussed in the literature on free will and moral responsibility.
  •  75
    Libertarianism about free will is the conjunction of two theses: the existence of free will is incompatible with the truth of determinism, and at least some human beings sometimes exercise free will (or act freely, for short). 1 Some libertarian views feature agent causation, others maintain that free actions are uncaused, and yet others – event-causal libertarian views – reject all views of these two kinds and appeal to indeterministic causation by events and states. 2 This article explores the…Read more
  •  54
    Tackling some central problems in the philosophy of action, Mele constructs an explanatory model for intentional behavior, locating the place and significance of such mental phenomena as beliefs, desires, reasons, and intentions in the etiology of intentional action. In the first part, Mele illuminates the connection between desire and action and defends detailed characterizations of irresistible desires and reasons for action. Mele argues for the viability of a causal approach to the explanatio…Read more
  •  391
    The author demonstrates that certain forms of irrationality - incontinent action and self-deception - which many philosophers have rejected as being logically or psychologically impossible, are indeed possible.