• The Logical Status of Conditionalization and its Role in Confirmation Commentary
    Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities 71 77-94. 2000.
  •  218
    Value and Agent-Relative Reasons
    Utilitas 7 (1): 31. 1995.
    In recent years the distinction between agent-relative and agent-neutral reasons has been taken by many to play a key role in distinguishing deontology from consequentialism. It is central to all universalist consequentialist theories that value is determined impersonally; the real value of any state of affairs does not depend on the point of view of the agent. No reference, therefore, to the agent or to his or her position in the world need enter into a consequentialist understanding of what ma…Read more
  • Psychology and Newtonian Methodology
    Journal of Mind and Behavior 16 (1): 35-43. 1995.
    According to Newton, the goals of natural philosophy comprise quantitative generalizations and causal knowledge, the latter being paramount. Quantitative generalizations are sometimes explanatory, in psychology as elsewhere . However, in psychology, they are not explanatory when the human subject is considered qua bearer of psychological states , but only when she is considered qua physical system. In the former case quantitative generalizations are, rather, to be causally explained. In this sen…Read more
  •  65
    A note on the two envelopes problem
    Theory and Decision 36 (1): 97-102. 1994.
  •  156
    Unprincipled Ethics
    In Brad Hooker & Margaret Olivia Little (eds.), Moral particularism, Oxford University Press. 2000.
  •  115
    Honoring and promoting values
    Ethics 102 (4): 835-843. 1992.
  •  82
    Benefits, holism, and the aggregation of value
    Social Philosophy and Policy 26 (1): 354-374. 2009.
    We reject Moorean holism about value—the view that the value of the whole does not equal the sum of the values of its parts. We propose an alternative aggregative holism according to which the value of a state of affairs is the sum of the values of its constituent states. But these constituents must be evaluated in situ
  •  504
    On defending deontology
    Ratio 11 (1). 1998.
    This paper comprises three sections. First, we offer a traditional defence of deontology, in the manner of, for example, W.D. Ross (1965). The leading idea of such a defence is that the right is independent of the good. Second, we modify the now standard account of the distinction, in terms of the agent-relative/agentneutral divide, between deontology and consequentialism. (This modification is necessary if indirect consequentialism is to count as a form of consequentialism.) Third, we challenge…Read more
  •  141
    Deontology
    In David Copp (ed.), The Oxford handbook of ethical theory, Oxford University Press. 2006.
  •  45
    The ranking of preference
    Philosophical Quarterly 40 (161): 495-501. 1990.
  •  134
  •  74
    Perspectives on a Pair of Envelopes
    Theory and Decision 43 (3): 253-277. 1997.
    The two envelopes problem has generated a significant number of publications (I have benefitted from reading many of them, only some of which I cite; see the epilogue for a historical note). Part of my purpose here is to provide a review of previous results (with somewhat simpler demonstrations). In addition, I hope to clear up what I see as some misconceptions concerning the problem. Within a countably additive probability framework, the problem illustrates a breakdown of dominance with respect…Read more
  • Book Review (review)
    Economics and Philosophy 14 (2): 342-349. 1998.
  •  114
    Introduction: Aspects of Rationality
    In Alfred R. Mele & Piers Rawling (eds.), The Oxford Handbook of Rationality, Oxford University Press. 2004.
    This article examines the nature of rationality. The domain of rationality is customarily divided into the theoretical and the practical. Whereas theoretical or epistemic rationality is concerned with what it is rational to believe, and sometimes with rational degrees of belief, practical rationality is concerned with what it is rational to do, or intend or desire to do. This article raises some of the main issues relevant to philosophical discussion of the nature of rationality. Discussions of …Read more
  •  70
  •  126
    Contours of the Practical
    In David Bakhurst, Margaret Olivia Little & Brad Hooker (eds.), Thinking about reasons: themes from the philosophy of Jonathan Dancy, Oxford University Press. pp. 240. 2013.
  • Steven Rappaport, Models and Reality in Economics (review)
    Philosophy in Review 20 279-281. 2000.
  •  87
    Decision theory and degree of belief
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences. forthcoming.
  •  24
    Robust Realisms and Realities
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 42 (1): 103-114. 1999.
  •  52
  •  115
    Deontology and value
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 47 197-208. 2000.
    Integration and coherence are central values in human existence. It would be a serious objection to any proposed way of life that it led to us being alienated or cut off from others or from some importan part of ourselves. Morality, with the strenuous demands it makes on us, is one area in which alienation is both particularly threatening and peculiarly undesirable. If morality cuts us off from some important part of ourselves then it appears unattractive, and if it cuts us off from others then …Read more
  •  279
    significant role for accomplishment thereby admits a ‘Trojan Horse’ (267).1 To abandon hedonism in favour of a conception of well-being that incorporates achievement is to take the first step down a slippery slope toward the collapse of the other two pillars of utilitarian morality: welfarism and consequentialism. We shall argue that Crisp’s arguments do not support these conclusions. We begin with welfarism. Crisp defines it thus: ‘Well-being is the only value. Everything good must be good for …Read more
  •  87
    There is a substantial literature on the Bayesian approach, and the application of Bayes'' theorem, to legal matters. However, I have found no discussion that explores fully the issue of how a Bayesian juror might be led from an initial "presumption of innocence" to the judgment (required for conviction in criminal cases) that the suspect is "guilty beyond a reasonable doubt". I shall argue here that a Bayesian juror, if she acts in accord with what the law prescribes, will virtually never reach…Read more