•  2204
    Toward a Theory of Medical Fallibility
    Hastings Center Report 5 (6): 13. 1975.
  •  1638
    The Religious Significance of Atheism
    with Paul Ricoeur
    Religious Studies 8 (1): 88-93. 1972.
  •  670
    Toward a Theory of Medical Fallibility
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1 (1): 51-71. 1976.
  •  546
    Three Rival Versions of Moral Enquiry
    Philosophy 66 (258): 533-534. 1991.
  •  539
    Contingency, Irony, and Solidarity by Richard Rorty (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 87 (12): 708-711. 1990.
  •  380
    Toward a theory of medical fallibility
    Journal of Medicine and Philosophy 1 (1): 13-23. 1976.
  •  344
    Partisan or Neutral? The Futility of Public Political Theory
    Philosophical and Phenomenological Research 60 (3): 731-734. 2000.
  •  325
    Difficulties in Christian Belief
    Philosophy 35 (134): 278-278. 1960.
  •  314
    Plain Persons and Moral Philosophy
    American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 66 (1): 3-19. 1992.
  •  294
    Charles Taylor and dramatic narrative: Argument and genre
    Philosophy and Social Criticism 44 (7): 761-763. 2018.
  •  289
    Pluralism and the Moral Mind
    The Proceedings of the Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy 1 9-18. 1999.
    Cultural pluralism has caused disturbing problems for philosophers in applied ethics. If moral sanctions, theories, and applications are culturally bound, then moral conflicts ensuing from cultural differences would seem to be irresolvable. Even human nature, good or evil, is not free from cultural determination. One way out of this pluralistic impasse is the expansion of the moral mind. It is the outlet taken by religion, the arts, and philosophy from the earliest time in human culture. In phil…Read more
  •  276
    On Being a Theistic Philosopher in a Secularized Culture
    Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association 84 23-32. 2010.
  •  257
    Is patriotism a virtue?
    In Derek Matravers & Jonathan Pike (eds.), Debates in Contemporary Political Philosophy: An Anthology, Routledge, in Association With the Open University. 1984.
    This is the text of The Lindley Lecture for 1984, given by Alasdair Maclntyre, a Scottish philosopher
  •  226
    A mistake about causality in social science
    with Andrei Korbut
    Russian Sociological Review 12 (1): 139-157. 2013.
    The article considers the problem of actions–beliefs link. As author shows, the widespread approach in social science, those origins can be traced back to Hume and Mill and which tries to reveal the causal relations between beliefs and actions, is mistaken. It is mistaken because it proposes that, firstly, beliefs and actions are distinct and separately identifiable social phenomena and, secondly, causal connection consists in constant conjunction. MacIntyre, instead, proposes, taking as a start…Read more
  •  220
    Social structures and their threats to moral agency
    Philosophy 74 (3): 311-329. 1999.
    Imagine first the case of J (who might be anybody, jemand). J used to inhabit a social order, or rather an area within a social order, where socially approved roles were unusually well-defined. Responsibilities were allocated to each such role and each sphere of role-structured activity was clearly demarcated. These allocations and demarcations were embodied in and partly constituted by the expectations that others had learned to have of those who occupied each such role. For those who occupied …Read more
  •  219
    Whose Justice? Which Rationality?
    University of Notre Dame Press. 1988.
    [This book] develops an account of rationality and justice that is tradition specific.-http://undpress.nd.edu.
  •  212
    Which God Ought We to Obey and Why?
    Faith and Philosophy 3 (4): 359-371. 1986.
  •  206
    Alasdair Macintyre on education: In dialogue with Joseph Dunne
    Journal of Philosophy of Education 36 (1). 2002.
    This discussion begins from the dilemma, posed in some earlier writing by Alasdair MacIntyre, that education is essential but also, in current economic and cultural conditions, impossible. The potential for resolving this dilemma through appeal to ‘practice’, ‘narrative unity’, and ‘tradition’(three core concepts in After Virtue and later writings) is then examined. The discussion also explores the relationship of education to the modern state and the power of a liberal education to create an ‘e…Read more
  •  185
    After virtue: a study in moral theory
    University of Notre Dame Press. 1984.
    This classic and controversial book examines the roots of the idea of virtue, diagnoses the reasons for its absence in modern life, and proposes a path for its recovery.
  •  181
    Sartre by Peter Caws (review)
    Journal of Philosophy 80 (12): 813-817. 1983.
  •  178
    Does Applied Ethics Rest on a Mistake?
    The Monist 67 (4): 498-513. 1984.
    ‘Applied ethics’, as that expression is now used, is a single rubric for a large range of different theoretical and practical activities. Such rubrics function partly as a protective device both within the academic community and outside it; a name of this kind suggests not just a discipline, but a particular type of discipline. In the case of ‘applied ethics’ the suggestive power of the name derives from a particular conception of the relationship of ethics to what goes on under the rubric of ‘a…Read more
  •  160
    The Seven Deadly Sins Today
    with Stanford M. Lyman and Henry Fairlie
    Hastings Center Report 9 (2): 28. 1979.
    Book reviewed in this article: The Seven Deadly Sins: Society and Evil. By Stanford M. Lyman. The Seven Deadly Sins Today. By Henry Fairlie.
  •  158
    Faith and Logic
    Philosophical Quarterly 9 (34): 90-91. 1959.
  •  143
    Relativism, Power and Philosophy
    Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association 59 (1). 1985.