•  14
    This book provides the first in-depth exploration of the importance of music for Ludwig Wittgenstein’s life and work. Wittgenstein’s remarks on music are essential for understanding his philosophy: they are on the nature of musical understanding, the relation of music to language, the concepts of representation and expression, on melody, irony and aspect-perception, and, on the great composers belonging to the Austrian-German tradition. Biography and philosophy, this work suggests that Wittgenst…Read more
  •  5
    Wittgenstein’s Reception of Wagner: Language, Music, and Culture
    In Sascha Bru, Wolfgang Huemer & Daniel Steuer (eds.), Wittgenstein Reading, De Gruyter. pp. 171-196. 2013.
  •  99
    ABSTRACTThis article retrieves, situates, and interprets Ludwig Wittgenstein's overlooked remarks about the composer Gustav Mahler, and connects them with Wittgenstein's philosophical perspective and practice, as well as with his musical aesthetics.
  •  665
    Chapter in Wittgenstein at the Movies, an in-depth explorations of two experimental films on Wittgenstein: Derek Jarman's Wittgenstein and Péter Forgács' Wittgenstein Tractatus.
  •  2
    Rylean Belief
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 26 198-203. 1978.
  •  1
    On ‘Morality and Class’
    Philosophical Studies (Dublin) 27 77-84. 1980.
  •  37
    Wittgenstein on 'Mistrusting One's Own Belief'
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 11 (4). 1981.
    Can one mistrust one's own belief? Wittgenstein says ‘No.’ He remarks: ‘One can mistrust one's own senses, but not one's own belief.’It is natural to think that this is not meant merely as a remark about our psychological abilities or inabilities; viz., that one can not, as a matter of psychological fact, help but trust one's own belief. Rather, one is inclined to take it as a ‘grammatical remark’ to the effect that it makes no sense to speak of trusting or mistrusting one's own belief.
  •  12
    Hypocricy and Privacy
    Journal of Philosophical Research 27 601-618. 2002.
    Hypocrisy and privacy are commonly thought to be completely different, yet it turns out to be surprisingly difficult to distinguish them. We consider various ways in which they might be differentiated, especially the attempt to do so on the basis of their moral standing. We argue, by case and through discussion, that there is more moral ambiguity about each concept than generally acknowledged. Finally, we offer some additional speculations about the similarities and differences between the two, …Read more
  •  59
    pour l'autre en nous et parmi nousAn apologia seeks to cover up the revolutionary moments in the course of history. The establishment of continuity is dear to its heart. It only gives importance to those elements of a work that have already generated an after-effect. It misses those points at which the transmission breaks down and thus misses those jags and crags that offer a handhold to someone who wishes to move beyond them.I am all the same convinced that these notes [in Culture and Value] ca…Read more
  •  32
    The Prayers and Tears of Jacques Derrida (review)
    Dialogue 39 (2): 397-399. 2000.
    Caputo’s book is enigmatic. It is, on the one hand, a remorseless screed directed against those who proclaim to the world “the totalizing truth or logos that engulfs the other.” As such, it contains predictable characterizations of a variety of logocentric villains as historically disparate as Plato and the “Polish Pope, John Paul II,” in which their contributions to philosophical discourse are alternatively parodied and vilified as being hostile to that spirit of openness to the “toute autre,” …Read more
  •  3
    No Title available: Dialogue
    Dialogue 48 (1): 214-216. 2009.
  • Reading Rousseau through the eyes of embarrassment
    British Journal of Aesthetics 34 (3). 1994.
  •  2
    D.F. Pears, Motivated Irrationality (review)
    Philosophy in Review 6 (1): 20-23. 1986.
  •  66
    On "Moral Expertise"
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 8 (1). 1978.
    Not so long ago it was fashionable to claim that it is not the moral philosopher's business to say what things are good or what actions we should perform. This view is succinctly stated by A. J. Ayer:There is a distinction, which is not always sufficiently marked, between the activity of a moralist, who sets out to elaborate a moral code, or to encourage its observance, and that of a moral philosopher, whose concern is not primarily to make moral judgments but to analyse their nature.On the othe…Read more
  • M.R. Haight, A Study Of Self-deception (review)
    Philosophy in Review 1 259-263. 1981.
  •  22
    Was wittgenstein a fideist? two views
    with Ken McGovern
    Sophia 41 (2): 41-54. 2002.
    Kai Nielsen and Felicity McCutcheon have each in their own way taken issue with the received view that Wittgenstein’s remarks on religious language are to be construed as a form of “fideism”. They each provide sharply divergent views on Wittgenstein’s remarks on the meaning of religious language and, indeed, the importance of religion itself. These differences, however, serve to bring into relief both Wittgenstein’s recognition of the genuinely descriptive nature of ordinary religious discourse …Read more
  • Jay Newman, Fanatics and Hypocrites Reviewed by
    Philosophy in Review 7 (9): 367-370. 1987.
  •  7
    Wittgenstein at the Movies: Cinematic Investigations (edited book)
    with Christina Stojanova
    Lexington Books. 2011.
    Wittgenstein at the Movies is centered on in-depth explorations of two intriguing experimental films on Wittgenstein: Derek Jarman's Wittgenstein and Péter Forgács' Wittgenstein Tractatus. The featured essays look at cinematic interpretations of Wittgenstein's life and philosophy in a manner bound to provoke the lively interest of Wittgenstein scholars, film theorists, students of film aesthetics and artistic modernism, and those concerned with the world of Cambridge in the first half of the twe…Read more
  •  28
    Irrationality (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 20 (3): 403-415. 1990.
  •  23
    Rorty on belief and self‐deception
    Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 464-473. 1974.
    In this note I argue that although Rorty's programme (Inquiry, Vol. 15, No. 4) to bring into focus the role that belief plays in self?deception is a salutary one, her actual claims obscure that role. It is also contended that Rorty fails to de?mythologize self?deception, since her account is either paradox?ridden or else describes a concept recognizably distinct from the concept of self?deception
  •  29
    Wittgenstein on belief
    Philosophical Papers 10 (1): 24-34. 1981.
  •  13
    Embarrassment and Self-Esteem
    Journal of Philosophical Research 15 341-349. 1990.
    Emotions are in as a philosophical topic. Yet the recent literature is bent on grand theorizing rather than attempting to explore particular emotions and their roles in our lives. In this paper, I aim to remedy this situation a little by exploring the emotion of embarrassment. First, I critically examine R.C. Solomon’s conceptual sketch and try to distinguish “embarrassment” from “shame”, “humiliation” and “being amused”. Secondly, I argue that “private embarrassment” is a coherent and useful id…Read more
  • Otto Weininger, On Last Things (review)
    Philosophy in Review 21 380-382. 2001.