•  34
    On the content of experience
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 75 (3). 2007.
    The intentionalist about consciousness holds that the qualitative character of experience
  •  18
    Alan Berger’s Terms and Truth covers various expressionsparticularly names and anaphoric pronouns, but also demonstratives and general termsas they occur in various linguistic contexts, including identity sentences, belief ascriptions, and negative existentials. A central thesis of Berger’s book is that all of these expressions are rigid designators. (So I assume that Berger would say, contrary to what the subtitle might suggest, that anaphoric reference is direct reference.).
  •  15
    Putting Things in Contexts
    Philosophical Review 112 (2): 191-214. 2003.
    Thanks to David Kaplan, we all know how to handle indexicals like ‘I’. ‘I’ doesn’t refer to an object simpliciter; rather, it refers to an object only relative to a context. In particular, relative to a context C, ‘I’ refers to the agent of C. Since different contexts can have different agents, ‘I’ can refer to different objects relative to different contexts. For example, relative to a context c whose agent is Gottlob Frege, ‘I’ refers to Frege; relative to a context c* whose agent is Alexius M…Read more
  • Never Been Kicked
    In Thomas E. Wartenberg (ed.), Fight Club, Routledge. 2011.
  • Hylomorphic Propositions
    In Chris Tillman & Adam Murray (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Propositions, Routledge. 2022.
  • E. E. Constance Jones on Existence in Fiction and Imagination
    Studia Semiotyczne (Semiotic Studies) 36 (1): 175-191. 2022.
  •  136
    Empty names
    Dissertation, UCLA. 2002.
    In my dissertation (UCLA 2002), I argue that, by appropriating Fregean resources, Millians can solve the problems that empty names pose. As a result, the debate between Millians and Fregeans should be understood, not as a debate about whether there are senses, but rather as a debate about where there are senses.
  •  2
    Ontology
    In Theodore Gracyk & Andrew Kania (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy and Music, Routledge. 2011.
  •  16
    Review of Consequences of Reference Failure (review)
    Philosophical Quarterly 71 (3): 666-669. 2021.
    Review of _Consequences of Reference Failure_. By McKinsey Michael. Routledge Studies in Contemporary Philosophy.
  •  38
    Works of Music: An Essay in Ontology: Book Reviews (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (4): 445-446. 2007.
  •  33
    Review of Trenton Merricks, Truth and Ontology (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2008 (2). 2008.
  •  22
    Review of Jerrold Katz, Sense, Reference, and Philosophy (review)
    Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews 2005 (1). 2005.
  •  584
    Against widescopism
    Philosophical Studies 125 (2): 167-190. 2005.
    Descriptivists say that every name is synonymous with some definite description, and Descriptivists who are Widescopers say that the definite description that a name is synonymous with must take wide scope with respect to modal adverbs such as “necessarily”. In this paper, I argue against Widescopism. Widescopers should be Super Widescopers: that is, they should say that the definite description that a name is synonymous with must take wide scope with respect to complementizers such as “that”. S…Read more
  •  807
    Defending 'Defending Musical Perdurantism'
    British Journal of Aesthetics 48 (1): 80-85. 2006.
    British Journal of Aesthetics (forthcoming Jan. 2008).
  •  107
    Soames’s new conception of propositions
    Philosophical Studies 173 (9): 2533-2549. 2016.
    In this paper, I argue that, when it comes to explaining what can be described as “representational” properties of propositions, Soames’s new conception of propositions—on which the proposition that Seattle is sunny is the act of predicating the property being sunny of Seattle and to entertain that proposition is to perform that act—does not have an advantage over traditional ones.
  •  153
    On sense and direct reference
    Philosophy Compass 1 (2): 171-185. 2006.
    Millianism and Fregeanism agree that a sentence that contains a name expresses a structured proposition but disagree about whether that proposition contains the object that the name refers to (Millianism) or rather a mode of presentation of that object (Fregeanism). Various problems – about simple sentences, propositional‐attitude ascriptions, and sentences that contain empty names – beset each view. To solve these problems, Millianism can appeal to modes of presentation, and Fregeanism can appe…Read more
  •  54
    Fusions and Ordinary Physical Objects
    with Bob Bright
    Philosophical Studies 125 (1): 61-83. 2005.
    In “Tropes and Ordinary Physical Objects”, Kris McDaniel argues that ordinary physical objects are fusions of monadic and polyadic tropes. McDaniel calls his view “TOPO”—for “Theory of Ordinary Physical Objects”. He argues that we should accept TOPO because of the philosophical work that it allows us to do. Among other things, TOPO is supposed to allow endurantists to reply to Mark Heller’s argument for perdurantism. But, we argue in this paper, TOPO does not help endurantists do that; indeed, w…Read more
  •  788
    Why So Tense about the Copula?
    Mind 114 (455). 2005.
    Mind 114.455 (July 2005): 703-708
  •  47
    A New Defence of the Modal Existence Requirement
    Synthese 154 (2): 335-343. 2007.
    In this paper, I defend the claim that an object can have a property only if it exists from two arguments, both of which turn on how to understand Plantinga’s notion of the α-transform of a property.
  •  538
    Fine individuation
    British Journal of Aesthetics 47 (2): 113-137. 2007.
    Jerrold Levinson argues that musical works are individuated by their context of origin. But one could just as well argue that musical works are individuated by their context of reception. Moderate contextualism, according to which musical works are individuated by context of origin but not by context of reception, thus appears to be an unstable position. And, although a more thoroughgoing contextualism, according to which musical works are individuated both by context of origin and by context of…Read more
  •  151
    Modality, Individuation, and the Ontology of Art
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 38 (4): 491-517. 2008.
    In 1988, Michael Nyman composed the score for Peter Greenaway’s film Drowning by Numbers (or did something that we would ordinarily think of as composing that score). We can think of Nyman’s compositional activity as a “generative performance” and of the sound structure that Nyman indicated (or of some other abstract object that is appropriately related to that sound structure) as the product generated by that performance (ix).1 According to one view, Nyman’s score for Drowning by the Numbers—th…Read more
  •  393
    Descriptivism, scope, and apparently empty names
    Philosophical Studies 156 (2): 283-288. 2011.
    Some descriptivists reply to the modal argument by appealing to scope ambiguities. In this paper, we argue that those replies don’t work in the case of apparently empty names like ‘Sherlock Holmes’.
  •  45
    Serial Fiction, Continued
    British Journal of Aesthetics 54 (1): 65-76. 2014.
    In ‘Truth, Relativism, and Serial Fiction’, Andrew McGonigal presents new data that a theory of truth in fiction should account for, and argues that the data is best accounted for by his relativist view. I argue against McGonigal’s relativist view and in favour of a more metaphysical view. The key feature of this view is that it is one on which the content of a work of fiction can change over time. Along the way I also argue against Ross Cameron’s contextualist view
  • Brutal identity
    In Stuart Brock & Anthony Everett (eds.), Fictional Objects, Oxford University Press. 2015.
  •  116
    The Extraordinary Impossibility of Sherlock Holmes
    Res Philosophica 93 (2): 335-355. 2016.
    In an addendum to Naming and Necessity, Saul Kripke argues against his earlier view that Sherlock Holmes is a possible person. In this paper, I suggest a nonstandard interpretation of the addendum. A key feature of this non-standard interpretation is that it attempts to make sense of why Kripke would be rejecting the view that Sherlock Holmes is a possible person without asserting that it is not the case that Sherlock Holmes is a possible person.