Cambridge University
Department of History and Philosophy of Science, St Edmund's College
PhD, 2023
CV
Cambridge, United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland
  •  41
    On the Challenges of Measurement in the Human Sciences
    Dissertation, University of Cambridge. 2023.
    Measurement practices are central to most sciences. In the human sciences, however, it remains controversial whether the measurement of human attributes—depression, happiness, intelligence, etc.—has been successful. Are, say, widely used depression questionnaires valid measuring instruments? Can we trust self-reported happiness scales to deliver quantitative measurements as it is sometimes claimed? These and related questions are till today hotly disputed. There are two main frameworks under whi…Read more
  •  20
    Well-Being Measurements and the Linearity Assumption: A Response to Wodak
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy. forthcoming.
    Wodak (2019) persuasively argues that we are not justified in believing that well-being measurements are linear. From this, he infers grave consequences for both political philosophy thought experiments and empirical psychological research. Here I argue that these consequences do not follow. Wodak’s challenges to the status of well-being measurements do not affect thought experiments, and well-being empirical researchers may be justified in making average comparisons even if their measurements a…Read more
  •  319
    Against Prohibition (Or, When Using Ordinal Scales to Compare Groups Is OK)
    The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. forthcoming.
    There is a widely held view on measurement inferences, that goes back to Stevens’s ([1946]) theory of measurement scales and ‘permissible statistics’. This view defends the following prohibition: you should not make inferences from averages taken with ordinal scales (versus quantitative scales: interval or ratio). This prohibition is general—it applies to all ordinal scales—and it is sometimes endorsed without qualification. Adhering to it dramatically limits the research that the social and bio…Read more
  •  320
    There is Cause to Randomize
    Philosophy of Science 89 (1). 2022.
    While practitioners think highly of randomized studies, some philosophers argue that there is no epistemic reason to randomize. Here I show that their arguments do not entail their conclusion. Moreover, I provide novel reasons for randomizing in the context of interventional studies. The overall discussion provides a unified framework for assessing baseline balance, one that holds for interventional and observational studies alike. The upshot: practitioners’ strong preference for randomized stud…Read more
  •  177
    On Measurement Scales: Neither Ordinal Nor Interval?
    Philosophy of Science 88 (5): 929-939. 2021.
    There is a received view on measurement scales. It includes both a classification of scales and a set of prescriptions regarding measurement inferences. This article casts doubt on the adequacy of this received view. To do this, I propose an epistemic characterization of the ordinal/interval distinction, that is, one in terms of researchers’ beliefs. This novel characterization reveals the ordinal/interval distinction as too coarse grained and thus the received view as too restrictive of a frame…Read more
  •  400
    Valid for What? On the Very Idea of Unconditional Validity
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 51 (2). 2021.
    What is a valid measuring instrument? Recent philosophy has attended to logic of justification of measures, such as construct validation, but not to the question of what it means for an instrument to be a valid measure of a construct. A prominent approach grounds validity in the existence of a causal link between the attribute and its detectable manifestations. Some of its proponents claim that, therefore, validity does not depend on pragmatics and research context. In this paper, I cast doubt o…Read more
  •  634
    Well-Ordered Science’s Basic Problem
    Philosophy of Science 87 (2): 365-375. 2020.
    Kitcher has proposed an ideal-theory account—well-ordered science (WOS)— of the collective good that science’s research agenda should promote. Against criticism regarding WOS’s action-guidance, Kitcher has advised critics not to confuse substantive ideals and the ways to arrive at them, and he has defended WOS as a necessary and useful ideal for science policy. I provide a distinction between two types of ideal-theories that helps clarifying WOS’s elusive nature. I use this distinction to argue …Read more