• From Puzzles to Principles?: Essays on Aristotle's Dialectic
    with Allan Bäck, Robert Bolton, J. D. G. Evans, Michael Ferejohn, Lenn E. Goodman, Edward Halper, Martha Husain, Gareth Matthews, and Robin Smith
    Lexington Books. 1999.
    Scholars of classical philosophy have long disputed whether Aristotle was a dialectical thinker. Most agree that Aristotle contrasts dialectical reasoning with demonstrative reasoning, where the former reasons from generally accepted opinions and the latter reasons from the true and primary. Starting with a grasp on truth, demonstration never relinquishes it. Starting with opinion, how could dialectical reasoning ever reach truth, much less the truth about first principles? Is dialectic then an …Read more
  •  50
    Spinoza's "Ethics": Don't Imitate God; There's a Model of Human Nature for You
    Philosophy and Theology 24 (2): 155-190. 2012.
    The Preface to Part 4 of Spinoza’s Ethics claims that we all desire to formulate a model of human nature. I show how that model serves the same function in ethics as the creed or articles of faith do in the Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, the function of allowing the imagination to provide a simularcrrum of rationality for finite, practical human beings.
  •  3
    Truth in Politics- Ethical Argument, Ethical Knowledge, and Ethical Truth
    Quest - and African Journal of Philosophy 16 (1-2): 220-237. 2002.
  •  7
    Review of Gene Sharp: The Politics of Nonviolent Action (review)
    Ethics 84 (3): 266-273. 1974.
  •  23
    The Politics of Nonviolent Action
    Political Theory 2 (4): 465-467. 1974.
  •  9
    Review of Peter Singer: Democracy and Disobedience (review)
    Ethics 86 (2): 175-179. 1976.
  •  9
    Spinoza and the Cunning of Imagination
    University of Chicago Press. 2018.
    Spinoza’s Ethics, and its project of proving ethical truths through the geometric method, have attracted and challenged readers for more than three hundred years. In Spinoza and the Cunning of Imagination, Eugene Garver uses the imagination as a guiding thread to this work. Other readers have looked at the imagination to account for Spinoza’s understanding of politics and religion, but this is the first inquiry to see it as central to the Ethics as a whole—imagination as a quality to be cultivat…Read more
  •  16
    The Crito dramatizes the impossibility, and the indispensability, of persuasion sby locating it between two extremes, Socrates and the Laws, the truths of philosophy and the force of politics. The question is whether those two limits are themselves inside or outside rhetoric. Can philosophy persuade, ormust it always be an alternative sto persuasion? Socrates insists on ignoring the opinion, and the power, of the many, and so the Laws have to show themselves as different from the opinion of the …Read more
  •  16
    The Charmides, searching for a definition of temperance, constantly confronts problems of reflexivity, transparency and opacity. Transparency and opacity structures the Charmides, from the dramatic beginning of Socrates peeking inside Charmides’ cloak, to Charmides’ initial depiction of sôphrosynê as concealing what one can do. The final two proposed definitions of temperance in the Charmides, self-knowledge and the knowledge of knowledge, are explicitly reflexive. That reflexivity is best under…Read more
  •  12
    Narratice, Rhetorical Argument, and Ethical Authority
    Law and Critique 10 (2): 117-146. 1999.
    The great challenge of rhetorical argument is to make discourse ethical without making it less logical. This challenge is of central importance throughout the full range of practical argument, and understanding the relation of the ethical to the logical is one of the principal contributions the humanities, in this case the study of rhetoric, can make to legal scholarship. Aristotle’s Rhetoric shows how arguments can be ethical and can create ethical relations between speaker and hearer. I intend…Read more
  •  46
  •  3
    8 Rhetoric, Hermeneutics, and Prudence in the Interpretation of the Constitution
    In eds Walter Jost and Michael J. Hyde (ed.), Rhetoric and Hermeneutics in Our Time: A Reader, Yale University Press. pp. 171-195
  •  4
    Aristotle's Politics V As An Example
    History of Political Thought 26 (2): 489-208. 2005.
    Virtuous people, unlike the rich and poor, do not form factions. What, then, is the role of philosophical argument within political argument? Politics V can be read as a handbook of practical advice that will help any rulers to stay in power, but it in fact develops a more subtle, and radical, role for philosophy in political argument. Like virtue, philosophy cannot be partisan, but the philosophical understanding of faction that Aristotle presents here makes its own contribution to political st…Read more
  •  62
    Aristotle's Rhetoric: An Art of Character
    University of Chicago Press. 1994.
    In this major contribution to philosophy and rhetoric, Eugene Garver shows how Aristotle integrates logic and virtue in his great treatise, the _Rhetoric._ He raises and answers a central question: can there be a civic art of rhetoric, an art that forms the character of citizens? By demonstrating the importance of the _Rhetoric_ for understanding current philosophical problems of practical reason, virtue, and character, Garver has written the first work to treat the _Rhetoric_ as philosophy and …Read more
  •  26
  •  50
    Aristotle's genealogy of morals
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 44 (4): 471-492. 1984.
  •  4
    Good Arguments (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 10 (4): 366-367. 1987.
  •  58
    Selected Issues in Logic and Communication (review)
    Teaching Philosophy 11 (4): 369-371. 1988.
  •  7
    Aristotle's "Rhetoric": Philosophical Essays (review) (review)
    Journal of the History of Philosophy 33 (4): 680-683. 1995.
    In lieu of an abstract, here is a brief excerpt of the content:680 JOURNAL OF THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY 33:4 OCTOBER 1995 cal advance over the criticisms of the Parmenidesas to say how the Theaetetusshould be called an "Eleatic" dialogue. The Sophist then reintroduces form, but in its epistemological aspect alone. Extensive use is made of the method of division, presented in the commentary as a rigorous method for precise definition, yet the Sophistfails to distinguish sophistry from philosophy.…Read more
  •  12
    The Crito dramatizes the impossibility, and the indispensability, of persuasion sby locating it between two extremes, Socrates and the Laws, the truths of philosophy and the force of politics. The question is whether those two limits are themselves inside or outside rhetoric. Can philosophy persuade, ormust it always be an alternative sto persuasion? Socrates insists on ignoring the opinion, and the power, of the many, and so the Laws have to show themselves as different from the opinion of the …Read more
  •  22
    Aristotle Politics Books V and VI (review)
    Ancient Philosophy 20 (1): 240-242. 2000.