•  6
    Quine's philosophy: an introduction
    Bloomsbury Academic. 2023.
    W.V. Quine is one of the leading figures of 20th century analytic philosophy, and still among the most influential. But his work can be challenging and complex, and indeed often misunderstood. In this updated introduction to Quine's thought, Gary Kemp examines his seemingly disparate views as a unified whole and offers a valuable guide for anyone approaching Quine for the first time.
  •  355
    Autonomy and privacy in Wittgenstein and Beckett
    Philosophy and Literature 27 (1): 164-187. 2003.
    No abstract available.
  •  73
    Propositions as Made of Words
    Erkenntnis 89 (2): 591-606. 2022.
    I argue that the principal roles standardly envisaged for abstract propositions can be discharged to the sentences themselves (and similarly for the meanings or senses of words). I discuss: (1) Cognitive Value: Hesperus-Phosphorus; (2) Indirect Sense and Propositional Attitudes; (3) the Paradox of Analysis; (4) the Picture Theory of the Tractatus; (5) Syntactical Diagrams and Meaning; (6) Quantifying-in. (7) Patterns of Use. I end with comparisons with related views of the territory.
  •  13
    Did Quine respond to the Kant-like question of what makes objectivity possible? And if so, what was his answer? I think Quine did have an answer, which is in fact a central theme in his philosophy. For his epistemology was not concerned with the question whether we have knowledge of the external world. His philosophy takes for granted that physics provides the most fundamental account of reality that we have. And like many positivists including Carnap, he takes that sort of question to have a fu…Read more
  •  480
    Trust and the appreciation of art
    Ratio 35 (2): 133-145. 2021.
    Does trust play a significant role in the appreciation of art? If so, how does it operate? We argue that it does, and that the mechanics of trust operate both at a general and a particular level. After outlining the general notion of ‘art-trust’—the notion sketched is consistent with most notions of trust on the market—and considering certain objections to the model proposed, we consider specific examples to show in some detail that the experience of works of art, and the attribution of art-rele…Read more
  • This edited volume includes 49 Chapters, each of which discusses the influence of a philosopher's reading of Wittgenstein in his/her philosophical works and the way such Wittgensteinian ideas have manifested themselves in those works.
  •  1
    This edited volume includes 36 Chapters, each of which discusses the influence of a philosopher's reading of Wittgenstein in his/her philosophical works and the way such Wittgensteinian ideas have manifested themselves in those works.
  •  62
    Observation Sentences Revisited
    Mind 131 (523): 805-825. 2021.
    I argue for an alternative to Quine’s conception of observation sentences, one that better satisfies the roles Quine envisages for them, and that otherwise respects Quinean constraints. After reviewing a certain predicament Quine got into in balancing the needs of the intersubjectivity of observation sentences with his notion of the stimulus meaning of an observation sentence, I push for replacing the latter with what I call the ‘stimulus field’ of an observation sentence, a notion that remains …Read more
  •  23
    Significance of the New Logic, by W. V. Quine
    Mind 129 (516): 1320-1327. 2020.
    In 1942, before his duties began in the USA Navy, W.V. Quine lectured at the Free School of Sociology and Politics of São Paulo. He wrote up the lectures in Por.
  •  347
    The Artistic Expression of Feeling
    Philosophia 49 (1): 315-332. 2020.
    In the past 60 years or so, the philosophical subject of artistic expression has generally been handled as an inquiry into the artistic expression of emotion. In my view this has led to a distortion of the relevant territory, to the artistic expression of feeling’s too often being overlooked. I explicate the emotion-feeling distinction in modern terms, and urge that the expression of feeling is too central to be waived off as outside the proper philosophical subject of artistic expression. Restr…Read more
  •  107
    Now with Venn Diagrams, expanded Extended Examples (nice work, Robert), and the latest trends in Rhetoric, post-truth etc. (nice work, Tracy).
  •  54
    In Favor of the Classical Quine on Ontology
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50 (2): 223-237. 2020.
    I make a Quinean case that Quine’s ontological relativity marked a wrong turn in his philosophy, that his fundamental commitments point toward the classical view of ontology that was worked out in most detail in hisWord and Object. This removes the impetus toward structuralism in his later philosophy.
  •  71
    Davidson's paratactic account of indirect quotation preserves the apparent relational structure of indirect speech but without assuming, in the Fregean manner, that the thing said by a sayer is a proposition. I argue that this is a mistake. As has been recognised by some critics, Davidson's account suffers from analytical shortcomings which can be overcome by redeploying the paratactic strategy as a means of referring to propositions. I offer a quick and comprehensive survey of these difficultie…Read more
  •  50
    Richard Wollheim was hardly alone in supposing that his account of pictorial depiction implies that a trompe-l’œil is not a depiction. I recommend removing this apparent implication by inserting a Kant-style version of aspect-perception into his account. I characterize the result as Neo-Wollheimian and retain the centrality of Wollheim’s notion of twofoldedness in the theory of depiction, but I demote it to a contingent feature of depictions and I criticize his employment of it for determining t…Read more
  •  23
    The unity of the proposition in the later Wittgenstein
    Conceptus: Zeitschrift Fur Philosophie 96. 2010.
  •  33
    Quine, Publicity, and Pre-Established Harmony
    ProtoSociology 34 59-72. 2017.
    ‘Linguistic meaning must be public’ – for Quine, here is not a statement to rest with, whether it be reckoned true or reckoned false. It calls for explication. When we do, using Quine’s words to piece together what he thought, we find that much too much is concealed by the original statement. Yes, Quine said ‘Language is a social art’; yes, he accepts behaviourism so far as linguistic meaning is concerned; yes, he broadly agrees with Wittgenstein’s anti-privacy stricture. But precisely what is b…Read more
  •  7
  •  68
    The Reference Book. By John Hawthorne and David Manley
    Philosophical Quarterly 63 (253): 827-830. 2013.
    © 2013 The Editors of The Philosophical QuarterlyMany moons ago, Bertrand Russell thought of reference in epistemic terms: to mean an object—to refer to it—one had to be acquainted with it; for it is ‘scarcely conceivable’ that one should judge without knowing what one is judging about. The rest of the relation between language and the world is conceived as denoting, a feature of linguistic expressions and bits of the world which crucially holds or fails to hold without affecting the reference o…Read more
  •  44
    Quine, by Peter Hylton
    Mind 119 (475): 794-798. 2010.
    (No abstract is available for this citation)
  •  105
    II—Hyperintensional Truth Conditions
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 88 (1): 57-68. 2014.
    A response to certain parts of Rumfitt : I defend Davidson's project in semantics, suggest that Rumfitt's use of sentential quantification renders his definition of truth needlessly elaborate, and pose a question for Rumfitt's handling of the strengthened Liar.
  •  23
    Is Everything a Set? Quine and Pythagoreanism
    The Monist 100 (2): 155-166. 2017.
    The view, in Quine, that all there are are pure sets is presented and endorsed.
  •  34
    Critical Thinking. A Concise Guide
    with Tracy Bowell
    Revue Philosophique de la France Et de l'Etranger 194 (1): 128-128. 2001.
  •  156
    Pushing Wittgenstein and Quine Closer Together
    Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy 2 (10). 2014.
    As against the view represented here by Peter Hacker and John Canfield, I urge that the philosophies of Quine and Wittgenstein can be reconciled. Both replace the orthodox view of language as resting on reference: Quine with the notion of linguistic disposition, Wittgenstein with the notions of grammar and forms of life. I argue that Wittgenstein's insistence, in the rule-following discussion, that at bottom these are matters of practice, of ‘what we do’, is not only compatible in a rough sort o…Read more
  •  93
    Frege's sharpness requirement
    Philosophical Quarterly 46 (183): 168-184. 1996.
  •  19
    Book reviews (review)
    British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (3): 300-303. 1999.
  •  200
    _Critical Thinking_ is a much-needed guide to thinking skills and above all to thinking critically for oneself. Through clear discussion, students learn the skills required to tell a good argument from a bad one. Key features include: *jargon-free discussion of key concepts in argumentation *how to avoid confusions surrounding words such as 'truth', 'knowledge' and 'opinion' *how to identify and evaluate the most common types of argument *how to spot fallacies in arguments and tell good reasonin…Read more
  •  242
    The aesthetic attitude
    British Journal of Aesthetics 39 (4): 392-399. 1999.