•  773
    Human aesthetic practices show a sensitivity to the ways that the appearance of an artefact manifests skills and other qualities of the maker. We investigate a possible origin for this kind of sensibility, locating it in the need for co-ordination of skill-transmission in the Acheulean stone tool culture. We argue that our narrative supports the idea that Acheulian agents were aesthetic agents. In line with this we offer what may seem an absurd comparison: between the Acheulian and the Quattroce…Read more
  •  767
    Art For Art’s Sake In The Old Stone Age
    Postgraduate Journal of Aesthetics 6 (1): 1-23. 2009.
    Is there a sensible version of the slogan “Art for art’s sake”? If there is, does it apply to anything? I believe that the answers to these questions are Yes and Yes. A positive answer to the first question alone would not be of interest; an intelligible claim without application does not do us much good. It’s the positive answer to the second question which is, I think, more important and perhaps surprising, since I claim to find art for art’s sake at a time well before most authorities would a…Read more
  •  583
    Learning from Fiction
    with Heather Ferguson, Jacopo Frascaroli, Stacie Friend, Kayleigh Green, and Lena Wimmer
    In Alison James, Akihiro Kubo & Françoise Lavocat (eds.), The Routledge Handbook of Fiction and Belief, Routledge. pp. 126-138. 2023.
    The idea that fictions may educate us is an old one, as is the view that they distort the truth and mislead us. While there is a long tradition of passionate assertion in this debate, systematic arguments are a recent development, and the idea of empirically testing is particularly novel. Our aim in this chapter is to provide clarity about what is at stake in this debate, what the options are, and how empirical work does or might bear on its resolution. We distinguish between merely influencing …Read more
  •  532
    Recreative Minds develops a philosophical theory of imagination that draws upon the latest work in psychology. This theory illuminates the use of imagination in coming to terms with art, its role in enabling us to live as social beings, and the psychological consequences of disordered imagination. The authors offer a lucid exploration of a fascinating subject.
  •  511
    The moral psychology of fiction
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 73 (2). 1995.
    What can we learn from fiction? I argue that we can learn about the consequences of a certain course of action by projecting ourselves, in imagination, into the situation of the fiction's characters
  •  468
    McGinn on delusion and imagination (review)
    Philosophical Books 47 (4): 306-313. 2006.
  •  457
    The Nature of Fiction
    Cambridge University Press. 1990.
    This important book provides a theory about the nature of fiction, and about the relation between the author, the reader and the fictional text. The approach is philosophical: that is to say, the author offers an account of key concepts such as fictional truth, fictional characters, and fiction itself. The book argues that the concept of fiction can be explained partly in terms of communicative intentions, partly in terms of a condition which excludes relations of counterfactual dependence betwe…Read more
  •  376
    Visible traces: Documentary and the contents of photographs
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 57 (3): 285-297. 1999.
  •  361
    Imagination, delusion and hallucinations
    In Max Coltheart & Martin Davies (eds.), Pathologies of Belief, Blackwell. pp. 168-183. 1991.
    Chris Frith has argued that a loss of the sense of agency is central to schizophrenia. This suggests a connection between hallucinations and delusions on the one hand, and the misidentification of the subject’s imaginings as perceptions and beliefs on the other. In particular, understanding the mechanisms that underlie imagination may help us to explain the puzzling phenomena of thought insertion and withdrawal. Frith sometimes states his argument in terms of a loss of metarepresentational capac…Read more
  •  357
  •  353
    Image and Mind: Film, Philosophy and Cognitive Science
    Cambridge University Press. 1995.
    This is a book about the nature of film: about the nature of moving images, about the viewer's relation to film, and about the kinds of narrative that film is capable of presenting. It represents a very decisive break with the semiotic and psychoanalytic theories of film which have dominated discussion. The central thesis is that film is essentially a pictorial medium and that the movement of film images is real rather than illusory. A general theory of pictorial representation is presented, whi…Read more
  •  262
    Unreliability refigured: Narrative in literature and film
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 53 (1): 19-29. 1995.
    Aims to improve an understanding of the theoretical issues in response to the influence of fiction. Four things in narrative unreliability; Relation between narration in literary fictions and film; Comprehension of narrative essentially a matter of intentional inference; Fictions misdescribed; Asymmetry between literature and film; Ambiguity and unreliability; Implied author and narrator.
  •  261
    Photography, painting and perception
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 49 (1): 23-29. 1991.
  •  257
    Impersonal imagining: A reply to Jerrold Levinson
    Philosophical Quarterly 44 (170): 79-82. 1994.
  •  236
    XI-Imagination as Motivation
    Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 102 (3): 201-216. 2002.
    What kinds of psychological states motivate us? Beliefs and desires are the obvious candidates. But some aspects of our behaviour suggest another idea. I have in mind the view that imagination can sometimes constitute motivation
  •  230
    What is fiction?
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 43 (4): 385-392. 1985.
  •  229
    Response to Jinhee Choi
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 59 (3). 2001.
  •  227
    Work and text
    Mind 100 (3): 325-340. 1991.
  •  191
    Review: Was Frege a Linguistic Philosopher? (review)
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 27 (1). 1976.
  •  182
    Mental simulation and motor imagery
    Philosophy of Science 64 (1): 161-80. 1997.
    Motor imagery typically involves an experience as of moving a body part. Recent studies reveal close parallels between the constraints on motor imagery and those on actual motor performance. How are these parallels to be explained? We advance a simulative theory of motor imagery, modeled on the idea that we predict and explain the decisions of others by simulating their decision-making processes. By proposing that motor imagery is essentially off-line motor action, we explain the tendency of mot…Read more
  •  180
    Fictional truth
    Philosophical Studies 50 (2). 1986.
  •  176
    Internal and external pictures
    with Catherine Abell
    Philosophical Psychology 12 (4): 429-445. 1999.
    What do pictures and mental images have in common? The contemporary tendency to reject mental picture theories of imagery suggests that the answer is: not much. We show that pictures and visual imagery have something important in common. They both contribute to mental simulations: pictures as inputs and mental images as outputs. But we reject the idea that mental images involve mental pictures, and we use simulation theory to strengthen the anti-pictorialist's case. Along the way we try to accou…Read more
  •  171
    Narratives and Narrators: A Philosophy of Stories
    Oxford University Press. 2010.
    This text offers a reflection on the nature and significance of narrative in human communication.
  •  166
    Desire in imagination
    In Tamar Gendler & John Hawthorne (eds.), Conceivability and Possibility, Oxford University Press. pp. 201-221. 2002.
  •  165
    Tragedy
    Analysis 70 (4): 632-638. 2010.
  •  163
    Both sides of the story: explaining events in a narrative
    Philosophical Studies 135 (1): 49-63. 2007.
    Our experience of narrative has an internal and an external aspect--the content of the narrative’s representations, and its intentional, communicative aetiology. The interaction of these two things is crucial to understanding how narrative works. I begin by laying out what I think we can reasonably expect from a narrative by way of causal information, and how causality interacts with other attributes we think of as central to narrative. At a certain point this discussion will strike a problem: o…Read more
  •  157
    On being fictional
    Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 55 (4): 425-427. 1997.
  •  151
    Visual imagery as the simulation of vision
    Mind and Language 10 (1-2): 25-44. 1995.
    Simulation Theory says we need not rely exclusively on prepositional knowledge of other minds in order to explain the actions of others. Seeking to know what you will do, I imagine myself in your situation, and see what decision I come up with. I argue that this conception of simulation naturally generalizes: various bits of our mental machine can be run‘off‐line’, fulfilling functions other than those they were made for. In particular, I suggest that visual imagery results when the visual syste…Read more