•  5
    Book reviews (review)
    with Michael Resnik, John Bigelow, Albert Lewis, Massimo Galuzzi, M. Franchella, Gabriel Nuchelmans, Alan Perreiah, Besprechung Von Christoph Demmerling, I. Grattan-Guinness, Michele Di Francesco, Thomas Oberdan, Wolfe Mays, John Martin, H. A. Ide, E. J. Lowe, J. Wolenski, Liliana Albertazzi, C. W. Kilmister, Christoph Demmerling, S. B. Russ, and Geregory Moore
    History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2): 221-263. 1993.
    Stewart Shapiro, Foundations without foundationalism: A case for second-order logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991. xvii + 277 pp. £35.00 A. Diaz, J, Echeverria and A. Ibarra, Structures in...
  •  346
    Where do sets come from?
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 56 (1): 150-175. 1991.
    A model-theoretic approach to the semantics of set-theoretic discourse.
  •  14
    Book Reviews (review)
    with Robin Smith, N. J. Green-Pedersen, David Holdcroft, Rezensiert von Peter Schroeder-Heister, Peter Loptson, Recensione di Corrado Mangione, P. M. Simons, and G. J. Tee
    History and Philosophy of Logic 5 (2): 233-263. 1984.
    Albert Menne and Niels Öffenberger, Zur modernen Deutung der aristotelischen Logik. Band I:Über den Folgerungsbegriff in der aristotelischen Logik. Hildesheim and New York: Georg Olms Verlag, 1982. 220 pp. DM 48.Klaus Jacobi, Die Modalbegriffe in den logischen Schriften des Wilhelm von Shyreswood und in anderen Kompendien des 12. und 13. Jahrhunderts. Funktionsbestimmung und Gebrauch in der logischen Analyse. Leiden and KÖln: E.J. Brill, 1980. xiii + 528 pp. HFL 140.Nineteenth – Century Contrast…Read more
  •  219
    Cardinality logics. Part II: Definability in languages based on `exactly'
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 (3): 765-784. 1988.
  •  205
    Stewart Shapiro’s Philosophy of Mathematics (review)
    Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 65 (2). 2002.
    Two slogans define structuralism: contemporary mathematics studies structures; mathematical objects are places in those structures. Shapiro’s version of structuralism posits abstract objects of three sorts. A system is “a collection of objects with certain relations” between these objects. “An extended family is a system of people with blood and marital relationships.” A baseball defense, e.g., the Yankee’s defense in the first game of the 1999 World Series, is a also a system, “a collection of …Read more
  •  238
    Cut-conditions on sets of multiple-alternative inferences
    Mathematical Logic Quarterly 68 (1). 2022.
    I prove that the Boolean Prime Ideal Theorem is equivalent, under some weak set-theoretic assumptions, to what I will call the Cut-for-Formulas to Cut-for-Sets Theorem: for a set F and a binary relation |- on Power(F), if |- is finitary, monotonic, and satisfies cut for formulas, then it also satisfies cut for sets. I deduce the CF/CS Theorem from the Ultrafilter Theorem twice; each proof uses a different order-theoretic variant of the Tukey- Teichmüller Lemma. I then discuss relationships betwe…Read more
  •  399
    One-step Modal Logics, Intuitionistic and Classical, Part 1
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (5): 837-872. 2021.
    This paper and its sequel “look under the hood” of the usual sorts of proof-theoretic systems for certain well-known intuitionistic and classical propositional modal logics. Section 1 is preliminary. Of most importance: a marked formula will be the result of prefixing a formula in a propositional modal language with a step-marker, for this paper either 0 or 1. Think of 1 as indicating the taking of “one step away from 0.” Deductions will be constructed using marked formulas. Section 2 prese…Read more
  •  300
    One-Step Modal Logics, Intuitionistic and Classical, Part 2
    Journal of Philosophical Logic 50 (5): 873-910. 2021.
    Part 1 [Hodes, 2021] “looked under the hood” of the familiar versions of the classical propositional modal logic K and its intuitionistic counterpart. This paper continues that project, addressing some familiar classical strengthenings of K and GL), and their intuitionistic counterparts. Section 9 associates two intuitionistic one-step proof-theoretic systems to each of the just mentioned intuitionistic logics, this by adding for each a new rule to those which generated IK in Part 1. For the sys…Read more
  •  129
    Jan von Plato and Sara Negri, Structural Proof Theory (review)
    Philosophical Review 115 (2): 255-258. 2006.
  •  60
    Intensional Mathematics. Stewart Shapiro (review)
    Philosophy of Science 56 (1): 177-178. 1989.
  •  21
    Book Review. Principles of Intuitionism. Michael Dummett (review)
    Philosophical Review 91 (2): 253-62. 1982.
  •  226
    Where Do the Cardinal Numbers Come From?
    Synthese 84 (3): 347-407. 1990.
    This paper presents a model-theoretic semantics for discourse "about" natural numbers, one that captures what I call "the mathematical-object picture", but avoids what I can "the mathematical-object theory".
  •  50
  •  257
    Where AR is the set of arithmetic Turing degrees, 0 (ω ) is the least member of { $\mathbf{\alpha}^{(2)}|\mathbf{a}$ is an upper bound on AR}. This situation is quite different if we examine HYP, the set of hyperarithmetic degrees. We shall prove (Corollary 1) that there is an a, an upper bound on HYP, whose hyperjump is the degree of Kleene's O. This paper generalizes this example, using an iteration of the jump operation into the transfinite which is based on results of Jensen and is detailed …Read more
  •  63
    Ontological Reduction (review)
    Philosophical Review 84 (3): 439. 1975.
  •  19
    Book Review. Reflections. Kurt Godel. (review)
    THe Journal for Symbolic Logic 54 (3): 1095-98. 1989.
  •  47
    Book Review. Abstract Objects. Bob Hale. (review)
    International Studies in Philosophy 24 (3): 146-48. 1992.
  •  482
    More about uniform upper Bounds on ideals of Turing degrees
    Journal of Symbolic Logic 48 (2): 441-457. 1983.
    Let I be a countable jump ideal in $\mathscr{D} = \langle \text{The Turing degrees}, \leq\rangle$ . The central theorem of this paper is: a is a uniform upper bound on I iff a computes the join of an I-exact pair whose double jump a (1) computes. We may replace "the join of an I-exact pair" in the above theorem by "a weak uniform upper bound on I". We also answer two minimality questions: the class of uniform upper bounds on I never has a minimal member; if ∪ I = L α [ A] ∩ ω ω for α admissible …Read more