•  88
    Two miracles of general relativity
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 64 14-25. 2018.
    We approach the physics of \emph{minimal coupling} in general relativity, demonstrating that in certain circumstances this leads to violations of the \emph{strong equivalence principle}, which states that, in general relativity, the dynamical laws of special relativity can be recovered at a point. We then assess the consequences of this result for the \emph{dynamical perspective on relativity}, finding that potential difficulties presented by such apparent violations of the strong equivalence pr…Read more
  •  92
    What makes a theory physically “complete”?
    with Andrew Elby and Sara Foster
    Foundations of Physics 23 (7): 971-985. 1993.
    Three claims about what makes a theory “physically complete” are (1) Shimony's assertion that a complete theory says “all there is to say” about nature; (2) EPR's requirement that a complete theory describe all “elements of reality”; and (3) Ballentine and Jarrett's claim that a “predictively complete” theory must obey a condition used in Bell deviations. After introducing “statistical completeness” as a partial formalization of (1), we explore the logical and motivational relationships connecti…Read more
  •  67
    Nonlocality and Gleason's lemma. Part I. Deterministic theories
    with G. Svetlichny
    Foundations of Physics 20 (11): 1379-1387. 1990.
    J. S. Bell's classic 1966 review paper on the foundations of quantum mechanics led directly to the Bell nonlocality theorem. It is not widely appreciated that the review paper contained the basic ingredients needed for a nonlocality result which holds in certain situations where the Bell inequality is not violated. We present in this paper a systematic formulation and evaluation of an argument due to Stairs in 1983, which establishes a nonlocality result based on the Bell-Kochen-Specker “paradox…Read more
  •  61
    Bohm particles and their detection in the light of neutron interferometry
    with C. Dewdney and G. Horton
    Foundations of Physics 25 (2): 329-347. 1995.
    Properties sometimes attributed to the “particle” aspect of a neutron, e.g., mass and magnetic moment, cannot straightforwardly be regarded in the Bohm interpretation of quantum mechanics as localized at the hypothetical position of the particle. This is shown by examining a series of effects in neutron interferometry. A related thought-experiment also provides a variation of a recent demonstration that which-way detectors can appear to behave anomolously in the Bohm theory
  •  5
    Book review (review)
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 (4): 979-982. 2007.
  •  163
    Boltzmann's H-theorem, its discontents, and the birth of statistical mechanics
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 40 (2): 174-191. 2009.
  •  85
    Do the bell inequalities require the existence of joint probability distributions?
    with George Svetlichny, Michael Redhead, and Jeremy Butterfield
    Philosophy of Science 55 (3): 387-401. 1988.
    Fine has recently proved the surprising result that satisfaction of the Bell inequality in a Clauser-Horne experiment implies the existence of joint probabilities for pairs of noncommuting observables in the experiment. In this paper we show that if probabilities are interpreted in the von Mises-Church sense of relative frequencies on random sequences, a proof of the Bell inequality is nonetheless possible in which such joint probabilities are assumed not to exist. We also argue that Fine's theo…Read more
  •  52
    Non-locality from an analogue of the quantum Zeno effect
    with E. J. Squires and L. Hardy
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 25 (3): 425-435. 1994.
  •  99
    The Dynamical Approach to Spacetime Theories
    with James Read
    In Eleanor Knox & Alastair Wilson (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Physics, Routledge. 2022.
    We review the dynamical approach to spacetime theories---in particular, its origins in the development of special relativity, its opposition to the contemporary `geometrical' approach, and the manner in which it plays out in general relativity. In addition, we demonstrate that the approach is compatible with the `angle bracket school'.
  •  155
    Mindful of Quantum Possibilities
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (2): 189-199. 1996.
  •  188
    Philosophical foundations of quantum field theory (edited book)
    with Rom Harré
    Oxford University Press. 1988.
    Quantum field theory, one of the most rapidly developing areas of contemporary physics, is full of problems of great theoretical and philosophical interest. This collection of essays is the first systematic exploration of the nature and implications of quantum field theory. The contributors discuss quantum field theory from a wide variety of standpoints, exploring in detail its mathematical structure and metaphysical and methodological implications.
  •  1
    Editorial
    Foundations of Physics 48 (5): 479-480. 2018.
  •  9
    Editorial
    Foundations of Physics 48 (5): 479-480. 2018.
  •  40
    Physical Relativity explores the nature of the distinction at the heart of Einstein's 1905 formulation of his special theory of relativity: that between kinematics and dynamics. Einstein himself became increasingly uncomfortable with this distinction, and with the limitations of what he called the 'principle theory' approach inspired by the logic of thermodynamics. A handful of physicists and philosophers have over the last century likewise expressed doubts about Einstein's treatment of the rela…Read more
  • Philosophical Foundations of Quantum Theory
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (1): 137-139. 1992.
  •  25
    Proper and improper separability
    with Christopher Gordon Timpson
    The distinction between proper and improper mixtures is a staple of the discussion of foundational questions in quantum mechanics. Here we note an analogous distinction in the context of the theory of entanglement. The terminology of `proper' versus `improper' separability is proposed to mark the distinction.
  •  219
    Solving the measurement problem: De broglie-Bohm loses out to Everett (review)
    Foundations of Physics 35 (4): 517-540. 2004.
    The quantum theory of de Broglie and Bohm solves the measurement problem, but the hypothetical corpuscles play no role in the argument. The solution finds a more natural home in the Everett interpretation.
  •  42
    Building with quantum correlations
    with Christopher G. Timpson
    'Correlations without correlata' is an influential way of thinking of quantum entanglement as a form primitive correlation which nonetheless maintains locality of quantum theory. A number of arguments have sought to suggest that such a view leads either to internal inconsistency or to conflict with the empirical predictions of quantum mechanics. Here wew explicate and provide a partial defence of the notion, arguing that these objections import unwarranted conceptions of correlation properties a…Read more
  •  136
    Entanglement and relativity
    with Christopher Gordon Timpson
    This paper surveys some of the questions that arise when we consider how entanglement and relativity are related via the notion of non-locality. We begin by reviewing the role of entangled states in Bell inequality violation and question whether the associated notions of non-locality lead to problems with relativity. The use of entanglement and wavefunction collapse in Einstein's famous incompleteness argument is then considered, before we go on to see how the issue of non-locality is transforme…Read more
  •  18
    When is a Physical Theory Relativistic?
    with Roland Sypel
    PSA: Proceedings of the Biennial Meeting of the Philosophy of Science Association 1992. 1992.
    Considerable work within the modern 'space-time theory' approach to relativity physics has been devoted to clarifying the role and meaning of the principle of relativity. Two recent discussions of the principle within this approach, due to Arntzenius (1990) and Friedman (1983), are found to contain difficulties.
  •  164
    The Philosophy of Vacuum (edited book)
    Oxford University Press. 1991.
    The vacuum is fast emerging as the central structure of modern physics. This collection brings together philosophically-minded specialists who engage these issues in the context of classical gravity, quantum electrodynamics, and the grand unification program. The vacuum emerges as the synthesis of concepts of space, time, and matter; in the context of relativity and the quantum this new synthesis represents a structure of the most intricate and novel complexity. This book is a work in modern met…Read more
  •  34
    Nonlocality in Quantum Mechanics
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 65 (1). 1991.
  • Nonlocality in Quantum Mechanics
    Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 65 119-159. 1991.
  •  272
    Relationalism rehabilitated? I: Classical mechanics
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 53 (2): 183--204. 2002.
    The implications for the substantivalist–relationalist controversy of Barbour and Bertotti's successful implementation of a Machian approach to dynamics are investigated. It is argued that in the context of Newtonian mechanics, the Machian framework provides a genuinely relational interpretation of dynamics and that it is more explanatory than the conventional, substantival interpretation. In a companion paper (Pooley [2002a]), the viability of the Machian framework as an interpretation of relat…Read more
  •  27
    Since the 1909 work of Carathéodory, formulations of thermodynamics have gained ground which highlight the role of the the binary relation of adiabatic accessibility between equilibrium states. A feature of Carathéodory's system is that the version therein of the second law contains an ambiguity about the nature of irreversible adiabatic processes, making it weaker than the traditional Kelvin-Planck statement of the law. This paper attempts first to clarify the nature of this ambiguity, by defin…Read more
  •  94
    The non-relativistic limits of the Maxwell and Dirac equations: the role of Galilean and gauge invariance
    with Peter Holland
    Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 34 (2): 161-187. 2003.
    The aim of this paper is to illustrate four properties of the non-relativistic limits of relativistic theories: that a massless relativistic field may have a meaningful non-relativistic limt, that a relativistic field may have more than one non-relativistic limit, that coupled relativistic systems may be "more relativistic" than their uncoupled counterparts, and that the properties of the non-relativistic limit of a dynamical equation may differ from those obtained when the limiting equation is …Read more
  •  7
    What makes a physical theory “complete”
    with Andrew Elby and Sara Foster
    Foundations of Physics 23 (7): 971-985. 1993.
  •  163
    Why special relativity should not be a template for a fundamental reformulation of quantum mechanics
    with Christopher G. Timpson
    In William Demopoulos & Itamar Pitowsky (eds.), Physical Theory and its Interpretation, Springer. pp. 29-42. 2006.
    In a comparison of the principles of special relativity and of quantum mechanics, the former theory is marked by its relative economy and apparent explanatory simplicity. A number of theorists have thus been led to search for a small number of postulates - essentially information theoretic in nature - that would play the role in quantum mechanics that the relativity principle and the light postulate jointly play in Einstein's 1905 special relativity theory. The purpose of the present paper is to…Read more
  •  91
    The notion that the metric field in general relativity can be understood as a property of space-time rests on a feature of the theory sometimes called universal coupling—the claim that rods and clocks “measure” the metric in a way that is independent of their constitution. It is pointed out that this feature is not strictly a consequence of the central dynamical tenets of the theory, and argued that the metric field would better be regarded as a field in space-time, rather than as the very fabri…Read more