•  364
    Population and Having Children Now
    Journal of Practical Ethics 5 (2): 49-61. 2017.
    This paper aims to state the obvious – the commonsense, rational approach to child-producing. We have no general obligation to promote either the “general happiness” or the equalization of this and that. We have children if we want them, if their life prospects are decent – and if we can afford them, which is a considerable part of their life prospects being OK – and provided that in doing so we do not inflict injury on others. It’s extremely difficult to do this latter, but affording them, in r…Read more
  •  843
    Resolving the Debate on Libertarianism and Abortion
    Libertarian Papers 8 267-272. 2016.
    I take issue with the view that libertarian theory does not imply any particular stand on abortion. Liberty is the absence of interference with people’s wills—interests, wishes, and desires. Only entities that have such are eligible for the direct rights of libertarian theory. Foetuses do not; and if aborted, there is then no future person whose rights are violated. Hence the “liberal” view of abortion: women (especially) may decide whether to bear the children they have conceived. Birth is a go…Read more
  •  53
    Aesthetics, Charity, Utility, and Distributive Justice
    The Monist 56 (4): 527-551. 1972.
    As I sit down to begin this essay, the strains of “Tristan und Isolde” are still ringing in my ears; meanwhile, another dozen or so Pakistanian refugees have died for lack of sufficient food, shelter, or medical attention, probably, during the time it will have taken to compose this paragraph. The Isolde in that performance commanded, probably, a fee of four or five thousand dollars; each member of the audience paid, on the average, perhaps ten dollars to see the performance. This works out, pro…Read more
  •  17
    Professor Filice’s Defense of Pacifism: A Comment
    Journal of Philosophical Research 17 483-491. 1992.
  •  18
    Self-Love and Self-Respect
    Dialogue 21 (3): 531-544. 1982.
  •  17
    Liberal-Conservative: The Real Controversy (review)
    Journal of Value Inquiry 34 (2/3): 167-188. 2000.
  •  30
    We Don’t Owe Them a Thing!
    The Monist 86 (3): 419-433. 2003.
    The discovery that people far away are in bad shape seems to generate a sense of guilt on the part of many articulate people in our part of the world, even though they are no worse off now that we’ve heard about them than they had been before. I will take it as given that we are certainly responsible for evils we inflict on others, no matter where, and that we owe those people compensation. Not all similarly agree that it is not in general our duty to make other people better off, and therefore …Read more
  •  1
    O obronie poprzez odstraszanie jądrowe
    Etyka 25 271-285. 1990.
    At the present time and for the foreseeable future, likely, there is no defence, strictly speaking, against nuclear weapons. Nations facing a threat of attack involving nuclear weapons, therefore, have only three alternatives: resort to deterrence, try to get by with conventional defences, or surrender. It is discussable which of these is the most prudent option for any given nation, but I argue that we cannot accept any view entailing that the first is not a right. What we can do, however, is t…Read more
  •  1
    Drugs and Responsibility
    In S. Luper-Foy C. Brown (ed.), Drugs, Morality, and the Law, Garland. pp. 3--24. 1994.
  •  44
    Reiman on Labor, Value, and the Difference Principle
    The Journal of Ethics 18 (1): 47-74. 2014.
    In As Free and as Just as Possible: The Theory of Marxian Liberalism, Jeffrey Reiman proposes to develop a theory of “Marxian Liberalism.” ‘Liberalism’ here is defined by the principle that “sane adult human beings should be free in the sense of free from coercion that would block their ability to act on the choices they make.” While the idea of coercion could use some glossing, it is not obvious that poverty, unemployment, racism, and sexism are as such coercive. In this book, it is, very broad…Read more
  •  29
    Introduction
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (2): 233-235. 2011.
  •  307
    Utilitarianism and new generations
    Mind 76 (301): 62-72. 1967.
  •  9
    Moral Relativity (review)
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17 (1): 235-257. 1987.
  •  24
    The general thrust of Neil Levy's paper is that a certain amount of paternalism should be viewed as compatible with liberalism.1 I am not quite convinced that what he is defending is properly paternalism. In addition, I am not entirely sure what his proposal is. Here are a few comments about several points in the paper.1. A possibly small question is worth raising when Levy says, ‘That is, the state may not interfere with individuals’ actions, even to promote their own conception of the good. Th…Read more
  •  54
    The Right to be Old and the Right to Have Young
    Tulane Studies in Philosophy 31 183-217. 1982.
  •  49
    Morality and utility
    Johns Hopkins University Press. 1967.
    This book is a general account of utilitarianism. It claims to provide a justification of the theses in Mill's On Liberty in utilitarian terms. There are several innovations relative to prevailing utilitarian literature of the day.
  •  2
    Book Review: Desert and Justice by Serena Olsaretti (review)
    Ethics 115 (1): 151-157. 2004.
  •  29
    Response
    International Journal of Applied Philosophy 25 (2): 259-272. 2011.
    Gibbard accuses me of having an “extreme” view of property rights, even though he agrees that liberty is a good thing. But is it good enough to justify excluding handouts to the poor? He thinks not. I argue that the “social contract” idea of justice, which he in general shares, would underwrite the sort of strong property rights I plump for—noting that voluntary assistance to the poor (or anyone) is, after all, not only perfectly acceptable but much to be commended. I believe I agree entirely wi…Read more
  •  54
    Equality vs. Liberty: Advantage, Liberty
    Social Philosophy and Policy 2 (1): 33. 1984.
    The subject of this essay is political, and therefore social, philosophy; and therefore, ethics. We want to know whether the right thing for a society to do is to incorporate in its structure requirements that we bring about equality, or liberty, or both if they are compatible, and if incompatible then which if either, or what sort of mix if they can to some degree be mixed. But this fairly succinct statement of the issue before us requires considerable clarification, even as a statment of the i…Read more
  •  72
    Three Analysis Retributivists
    Analysis 34 (6). 1974.
  •  161
    Animal Rights
    Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7 (1). 1977.
    What do we owe to the lower animals, if anything? The issues raised by this question are among the most fascinating and fundamental in ethical theory. They provide a real watershed for the moral philosopher and, on perhaps the most widely professed view, a trenchant test of consistency in ethical practice. Among the virtues of these two challenging books is that they make painfully clear that there has been a paucity of clear and plausible argument in support of the nearly universal tendency of …Read more
  •  22
    Sterba on Liberty and Welfarism
    Analyse & Kritik 37 (1-2): 203-222. 2015.
    James Sterba advances several arguments designed to show that libertarianism, contrary to what this author and other libertarians think, actually implies support for welfarism and even egalitarianism. This discussion shows why his arguments do not work. There is preliminary discussion of our parameters: how much is Sterba claiming we have a minimum right to in the way of welfare? It is argued that if this is set very low, a libertarian society would easily eliminate the poverty he is concerned a…Read more