•  198
    Particularism in Question: an Interview with Jonathan Dancy
    with Jonathan Dancy and Andreas Lind
    Theoria 74 (1): 3-17. 2008.
    Jonathan Dancy works within almost all fields of philosophy but is best known as the leading proponent of moral particularism. Particularism challenges “traditional” moral theories, such as Contractualism, Kantianism and Utilitarianism, in that it denies that moral thought and judgement relies upon, or is made possible by, a set of more or less well-defined, hierarchical principles. During the summer of 2006, the Philosophy Departments of Lund University (Sweden) and the University of Reading (E…Read more
  •  196
    Goodness, Values, Reasons
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12 (4): 329-343. 2009.
    Contemporary value theory has been characterized by a renewed interest in the analysis of concepts like "good" or "valuable", the most prominent pattern of analysis in recent years being the socalled buck-passing or fitting-attitude analysis which reduces goodness to a matter of having properties that provide reasons for pro-attitudes. Here I argue that such analyses are best understood as metaphysical rather than linguistic and that while the buck-passing analysis has some virtues, it still fai…Read more
  •  129
    This work seeks to develop a Kantian ethical theory in terms of a general ontology of values and norms together with a metaphysics of the person that makes sense of this ontology. It takes as its starting point Kant’s assertion that a good will is the only thing that has an unconditioned value and his accompanying view that the highest good consists in virtue and happiness in proportion to virtue. The soundness of Kant’s position on the value of the good will is defended against criticisms direc…Read more
  •  125
    Leading Lives: On Happiness and Narrative Meaning
    Philosophical Papers 32 (3): 321-343. 2003.
    Abstract In contemporary moral philosophy, the standard way of understanding the constituents of the human good is in terms of a fairly limited number of features that contribute to our happiness independently of how they are situated in our lives. Even when this approach is supplemented by Moorean ideas about organic wholes, it still cannot do justice to the deep importance of how things are situated and even when meaning is seen as an important factor, it still tends to be treated as simply an…Read more
  •  114
    Future generations as rightholders
    Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 19 (6): 680-698. 2016.
  •  109
    Excellence and means: On the limits of buck-passing
    Journal of Value Inquiry 42 (3): 301-315. 2008.
    The article explores the limits of buck-passing analysis in evaluating value or goodness. It talks about the inability of back-passers to account for two important types of value or goodness, which include excellence and means. The use of delimiting strategy in buck-passing analysis in order to be in possession of goodness is discussed.
  •  108
    Ethical Theories and the Transparency Condition
    Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 12 (5): 449-462. 2009.
    Following John Rawls, writers like Bernard Williams and Christine Korsgaard have suggested that a transparency condition should be put on ethical theories. The exact nature of such a condition and its implications is however not anything on which there is any consensus. It is argued here that the ultimate rationale of transparency conditions is epistemic rather than substantively moral, but also that it clearly connects to substantive concerns about moral psychology. Finally, it is argued that o…Read more
  •  104
    Institutions, Ideology, and Nonideal Social Ontology
    Philosophy of the Social Sciences 49 (2): 137-159. 2019.
    Analytic social ontology has been dominated by approaches where institutions tend to come out paradigmatically as being relatively harmonious and mutually beneficial. This can however raise worries about such models potentially playing an ideological role in conceptualizing certain politically charged features of our societies as marginal phenomena or not even being institutional matters at all. This article seeks to develop a nonideal theory of institutions, which neither assumes that instituti…Read more
  •  68
    Good-making and organic unity
    Philosophical Studies 174 (6): 1499-1516. 2017.
    Since G. E. Moore introduced his concept of organic unity there has been some discussion of how one should best understand this notion and whether there actually are any organic unities in the Moorean sense. Such discussions do however often put general questions about part-whole relations to the side and tend to focus on interpreting our intuitive responses to possible cases of organic unity. In this paper the focus lies on the part-whole relation in valuable wholes and it is suggested that we …Read more
  •  68
    Leading a Life of One’s Own: On Well-Being and Narrative Autonomy
    Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 59 65-82. 2006.
    We all want things. And although we might disagree on just how significant our wants, desires, or preferences are for the matter of how well we fare in life, we would probably all agree on some of them having some significance. So any reasonable theory about the human good should in some way acknowledge this. The theory that most clearly meets this demand is of course preferentialism, but even pluralist theories can do so. However, then they will at the same time bring aboard a classical problem…Read more
  •  65
    Good Lives: Parts and Wholes
    American Philosophical Quarterly 38 (2). 2001.
  •  63
    Rules and Exceptions
    Theoria 65 (2-3): 127-143. 1999.
    Over the last decades the traditional emphasis on moral rules, or principles, has been attacked by particularists like Jonathan Dancy. I argue that particularists are correct in rejecting traditional attempts at moral codification, but that it is still possible to have a rule-oriented approach to morality if we distinguish between different ways in which features can be morally relevant. I suggest that there are first a limited number of features that can serve as basic moral reasons for action,…Read more
  •  57
    Contested Institutional Facts
    Erkenntnis 84 (5): 1047-1064. 2019.
    A significant part of contemporary social ontology has been focused on understanding forms of collective intentionality. It is suggested in this paper that the contested nature of some institutional matters makes this kind of approach problematic, and instead an alternative approach is developed, one that is oriented towards a micro-level analysis of the institutional constraints that we face in everyday life and which can make sense of how there can be institutional facts that are deeply contes…Read more
  •  57
    A distinction in value: Intrinsic and for its own sake1
    with Krister Bykvist, Garrett Cullity, Åsa Carlson, Klemens Kappel, Ulrik Kihlbom, Ian Law, Hans Mathlein, Derek Parfit, and Ingmar Persson
    In Toni Rønnow-Rasmussen & Michael J. Zimmerman (eds.), Recent Work on Intrinsic Value, Springer. pp. 115. 2005.
  •  55
    Social positions and institutional privilege as matters of justice
    European Journal of Political Theory 20 (3): 510-528. 2018.
    Liberal political theory is often understood as being underpinned by an individualistic social ontology, and it is sometimes objected that this type of ontology makes it difficult to address injust...
  •  52
    From Virtue to Decency
    Metaphilosophy 37 (5): 589-604. 2006.
    In her work on virtue ethics Rosalind Hursthouse has formulated an Aristotelian criterion of rightness that understands rightness in terms of what the virtuous person would do. It is argued here that this kind of criterion does not allow enough room for the category of the supererogatory and that right and wrong should rather be understood in terms of the characteristic behavior of decent persons. Furthermore, it is suggested that this kind of approach has the added advantage of allowing one to …Read more
  •  49
    Moral Disunitarianism
    Philosophical Quarterly 66 (264): 481-499. 2016.
  •  49
    Respect for Persons in Bioethics: Towards a Human Rights-Based Account
    Human Rights Review 18 (2): 171-187. 2017.
    Human rights have increasingly been put forward as an important framework for bioethics. In this paper, it is argued that human rights offer a potentially fruitful approach to understanding the notion of Respect for Persons in bioethics. The idea that we are owed a certain kind of respect as persons is relatively common, but also quite often understood in terms of respecting people’s autonomous choices. Such accounts do however risk being too narrow, reducing some human beings to a second-class …Read more
  •  46
    The independence of medical ethics
    Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy 22 (1): 5-15. 2019.
    This paper discusses the relation between medical ethics and general moral theory, the argument being that medical ethics is best seen as independent from general moral theory. According to this independence thesis, here explicated in terms of what is called a disunitarian stance, the very idea of applied ethics, which is often seen as underlying medical ethics, is misguided. We should instead think of medical ethics as a domain-specific ethical inquiry among other domain-specific ethical inquir…Read more
  •  45
    Patriarchy as Institutional
    Journal of Social Ontology 7 (2): 233-254. 2021.
    In considering patriarchy as potentially institutional and as a characteristic also of contemporary Western societies, a fundamental issue concerns how to make sense of largely informal institutions to begin with. Traditional accounts of institutions have often focused on formalized ones. It is argued here, however, that the principal idea behind one commonly accepted conception of institutions can be developed in a way that better facilitates an explication of informal institutions. When applie…Read more
  •  37
    On the Epistemic Legitimacy of Government Paternalism
    Public Health Ethics 11 (1): 27-34. 2018.
    Some contemporary paternalists argue in favor of government interventions based on how experimental psychologists and behavioral economists have found that our behavior often diverges from what would be predicted by rational-choice models. In this article it is argued that these findings can, more specifically, be used to identify decisional trouble spots where paternalist interventions may be legitimate. It is further argued that since the epistemic legitimacy of government paternalism ultimate…Read more
  •  35
    Rawlsian Constructivism: A Practical Guide to Reflective Equilibrium
    The Journal of Ethics 24 (3): 355-373. 2020.
    Many normative theorists want to contribute to making the world a better place. In recent years, it has been suggested that to realise this ambition one must start with an adequate description of real-life practices. To determine what should be done, however, one must also fundamentally criticise existing moral beliefs. The method of reflective equilibrium offers a way of doing both. Yet, its practical usefulness has been doubted and it has been largely ignored in the recent practical turn of no…Read more
  •  32
    Means Paternalism and the Problem of Indeterminacy
    Moral Philosophy and Politics 10 (1): 47-67. 2023.
    Many contemporary defenders of paternalist interventions favor a version of paternalism focused on how people often choose the wrong means given their own ends. This idea is typically justified by empirical results in psychology and behavioral economics. To the extent that paternalist interventions can then target the promotion of goals that can be said to be our own, such interventions are prima facie less problematic. One version of this argument starts from the idea that it is meaningful to a…Read more
  •  25
    Normative ethics usually presupposes background accounts of human agency, and although different ethical theorists might have different pictures of human agency in mind, there is still something like a standard account that most of mainstream normative ethics can be understood to rest on. Ethical theorists tend to have Rational Man, or at least some close relative to him, in mind when constructing normative theories. It will be argued here that empirical findings raise doubts about the accuracy …Read more
  •  25
    Principles of justice and the idea of practice-dependence
    Ethics and Global Politics 12 (3): 1-16. 2019.
    In recent years, several political theorists have argued that reasonable principles of justice are practice-dependent. In this paper it is suggested that we can distinguish between at least two main models for doing practice-dependent theorizing about justice, interpretivism and constructivism, and that they can be understood as based in two different conceptions of practices. It is then argued that the reliance on the notion of participants that characterizes interpretivism disables this approa…Read more