•  491
    The big bad bug: What are the humean's chances?
    with John Collins and Robert Pargetter
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44 (3): 443-462. 1993.
    Humean supervenience is the doctrine that there are no necessary connections in the world. David Lewis identifies one big bad bug to the programme of providing Humean analyses for apparently non-Humean features of the world. The bug is chance. We put the bug under the microscope, and conclude that chance is no special problem for the Humean.
  •  36
    Notes on the
    with Lucy Allais, Louise Antony, Elizabeth Barnes, Alexander Bird, Ross P. Cameron, John Campbell, and Roberto Casati
    In Robin Le Poidevin, Simons Peter, McGonigal Andrew & Ross P. Cameron (eds.), The Routledge Companion to Metaphysics, Routledge. 2009.
  •  85
    How not to be muddled by a meddlesome muggletonian
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 75 (4). 1997.
    Holton, we acknowledge, has given a good counter-example to a theory, and that theory is interesting and worth refuting. The theory we have in mind is like Smith's, but is more reductionist in spirit. It is a theory that ties value to Reason and to processes of reasoning, or inference - not to the recognition of reasons and acting on reasons. Such a theory overestimates the importance of logic, truth, inference, and thinking things through for yourself independently of any ideas about where you …Read more
  •  8
    Against the Will
    with Robert Pargetter and Susan Dodds
    Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 69 (4): 307-324. 1988.
  •  172
  •  61
    According to the new family of theories that emerged around the second half of the nineteenth century, time is more similar to space than it had been construed to be under the previous family of theories. These new theories of time treat time as being a “fourth dimension” that is much more like the three spatial dimensions than it was imagined to be under the older rival theories. Over the two centuries following Newton, the key concepts of graphs and the differential and integral calculus, tric…Read more
  • Book Reviews (review)
    with M. Scanlan, M. De Mora Charles, I. Grattan-Guinness, Ole Immanuel Franksen, Jan Woleński, Albert C. Lewis, P. Pagin, Francisco A. Rodriguez-Consuegra, Desmond Paul Henry, L. Albertazzi, E. J. Lowe, G. H. Helman, Gerardo Tango, Robert W. Bruch, P. Thom, John Divers, and Roberto Poli
    History and Philosophy of Logic 13 (2): 225-260. 1992.
    N. Denyer, Language, thought and falsehood in ancient Greek philosophy. London and New York: Routledge, 1991. xi + 222 pp. £35.00 Luis Vega, La trama de la demostración.. Madrid: 1990, Alianza Editorial, 413 pp. No price stated Daniel D. Merrill, Augustus De Morgan and the logic of relations. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1990. xi + 259 pp. Dfl. 185/$ 114.00/£64.00 Georg Cantor, Briefe. Edited by Herbert Meschkowski and Winfried Nilson. Berlin, etc: Springer‐Verlag, 1991, viii + 535 pp. DM 158. The selecte…Read more
  •  12
    Acquaintance with qualia
    with Robert Pargetter
    Theoria 56 (3): 129-147. 1990.
  •  5
    Book reviews (review)
    with Michael Resnik, Albert Lewis, Massimo Galuzzi, M. Franchella, Gabriel Nuchelmans, Alan Perreiah, Besprechung Von Christoph Demmerling, I. Grattan-Guinness, Michele Di Francesco, Thomas Oberdan, Wolfe Mays, John Martin, H. A. Ide, E. J. Lowe, J. Wolenski, Liliana Albertazzi, H. Hodes, C. W. Kilmister, Christoph Demmerling, S. B. Russ, and Geregory Moore
    History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2): 221-263. 1993.
    Stewart Shapiro, Foundations without foundationalism: A case for second-order logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991. xvii + 277 pp. £35.00 A. Diaz, J, Echeverria and A. Ibarra, Structures in...
  •  1
    Book reviews (review)
    with Michael D. Resnik, Albert C. Lewis, Massimo Galuzzi, M. Franchella, Gabriel Nuchelmans, Alan R. Perreiah, Besprechung Von Christoph Demmerling, I. Grattan-Guinness, Michele Di Francesco, Thomas Oberdan, Wolfe Mays, John N. Martin, H. A. Ide, E. J. Lowe, J. Woleński, Liliana Albertazzi, H. Hodes, C. W. Kilmister, Christoph Demmerling, S. B. Russ, and Geregory H. Moore
    History and Philosophy of Logic 14 (2): 221-263. 1993.
    Stewart Shapiro, Foundations without foundationalism: A case for second-order logic. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1991. xvii + 277 pp. £35.00 A. Diaz, J, Echeverria and A. Ibarra, Structures in...
  •  217
    Re-acquaintance with qualia
    with Robert Pargetter
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (3). 2006.
    Frank Jackson argued, in an astronomically frequently cited paper on 'Epiphenomenal qualia '[Jackson 1982 that materialism must be mistaken. His argument is called the knowledge argument. Over the years since he published that paper, he gradually came to the conviction that the conclusion of the knowledge argument must be mistaken. Yet he long remained totally unconvinced by any of the very numerous published attempts to explain where his knowledge argument had gone astray. Eventually, Jackson d…Read more
  •  142
    Real possibilities
    Philosophical Studies 53 (1). 1988.
  •  60
  •  25
    Meaning and Evidence
    Dialogue 15 (2): 203-225. 1976.
  •  108
    Believing in semantics
    Linguistics and Philosophy 2 (1): 101--144. 1978.
    This paper concerns the semantics of belief-sentences. I pass over ontologically lavish theories which appeal to impossible worlds, or other points of reference which contain more than possible worlds. I then refute ontologically stingy, quotational theories. My own theory employs the techniques of possible worlds semantics to elaborate a Fregean analysis of belief-sentences. In a belief-sentence, the embedded clause does not have its usual reference, but refers rather to its own semantic struct…Read more
  •  52
    I. Logic, rationality and ideology Herbert Marcuse once claimed that the ‘“rational” is a mode of thought and action which is geared to reduce ignorance, destruction, brutality, and oppression.’ He echoed a widespread folk belief that a world in which people were rational would be a better world. This could be taken as an optimistic empirical conjecture: if people were more rational then probably the world would be a better place (a trust that ‘virtue will be rewarded’, so to speak). However, it…Read more
  •  85
    Parfit, causation and survival
    Philosophia 28 (1-4): 467-476. 2001.
  •  477
    The world as one of a kind: Natural necessity and laws of nature
    with Brian Ellis and Caroline Lierse
    British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 43 (3): 371-388. 1992.
  •  442
    Challenging the myth that mathematical objects can be defined into existence, Bigelow here employs Armstrong's metaphysical materialism to cast new light on mathematics. He identifies natural, real, and imaginary numbers and sets with specified physical properties and relations and, by so doing, draws mathematics back from its sterile, abstract exile into the midst of the physical world.
  •  1
    PARSONS, T.: "Nonexistent Objects" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 60 (n/a): 94. 1982.
  •  23
    LEWIS, D.: "The Plurality of Worlds" (review)
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 65 (n/a): 208. 1987.
  •  98
    God and the new math
    Philosophical Studies 84 (2-3). 1996.
  •  24
    Language in the World: A Philosophical Enquiry
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 74 (1). 1996.
    What makes the words we speak mean what they do? Possible-worlds semantics articulates the view that the meanings of words contribute to determining, for each sentence, which possible worlds would make the sentence true, and which would make it false. M. J. Cresswell argues that the non-semantic facts on which such semantic facts supervene are facts about the causal interactions between the linguistic behaviour of speakers and the facts in the world that they are speaking about, and that the kin…Read more
  •  44
    II. Land, well-being and compensation
    Australasian Journal of Philosophy 68 (3): 330-346. 1990.
    This Article does not have an abstract